You are on page 1of 16

Econometrics and Business Cycle Empirics

Author(s): David F. Hendry


Source: The Economic Journal, Vol. 105, No. 433 (Nov., 1995), pp. 1622-1636
Published by: Wiley on behalf of the Royal Economic Society
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2235123
Accessed: 04-04-2016 22:07 UTC
REFERENCES
Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article:
http://www.jstor.org/stable/2235123?seq=1&cid=pdf-reference#references_tab_contents
You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references.
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
http://about.jstor.org/terms

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted
digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about
JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Wiley, Royal Economic Society are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to
The Economic Journal

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.139 on Mon, 04 Apr 2016 22:07:26 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

The Economic Journal, 105 (November), I622-I636. ) Royal Economic Society I995. Published by Blackwell
Publishers, io8 Cowley Road, Oxford OX4 iJF, UK and 238 Main Street, Cambridge, MA 02I42, USA.

ECONOMETRICS AND BUSINESS CYCLE


EMPIRICS*
David F. Hendry

Business cycle empirics have long been a central arena for the debate about the
roles of economic theory and econometrics in modelling economic time-series
data: some famous historical examples are Moore (I9I4), Keynes (I939) and
Koopmans (I947). Sources for potential disagreements include that the entire
economic system is involved, and unobservable stochastic 'forces' seem more
than usually prominent in determining the outcome. Not only do these
constitute two aspects about which it is hard to theorise, they are equally
difficult to model empirically. There are both positive arguments for and
negative arguments against according a dominant role to either 'theory' or
'evidence', not least because it is unclear what constitutes admissible instances
of either in the absence of the other. We first review what precludes a purely
theoretical approach, what prevents a purely empirical approach, and hence
why an interactive approach is imperative. Even so, both the relative
importance of the two ingredients and their substantive contents are likely to
remain, at issue.

First, concerning the economy, considerable empirical evidence suggests that


it is a dynamic, non-linear, high dimensional, and evolving entity, so studying
it is difficult. Society and social systems alter over time, laws change, and
technological innovations occur, so establishing any invariants of an economic

system is not easy. Such difficulties adversely afflict both theory and empirical
modelling.

Secondly, concerning the observations, time-series data in economics are


heterogeneous, non-stationary, time dependent, and interdependent, so it is
difficult to acquire knowledge from the available empirical information. Again,
such factors also make it hard to theorise about the properties of the underlying

system. A more direct critique of the empirical enterprise is that samples are
short and highly aggregated, economic magnitudes are inaccurately measured,
are subject to considerable revision, and important variables are not measured
or are unobservable, so inferences are both imprecise and tentative. Combined

with the simultaneity, non-constancy, and high dimensionality of economic


data, a purely empirical approach seems to many to be precluded. Other
criticisms of econometric approaches include worries about 'data mining', pretest biases, a lack of genuine identifiability, and 'collinearity'- sometimes
combined with a belief that theory can compensate. An overemphasis on a
* This research was financed in part by grants Rooo233447 and Boo2200I2 from the United Kingdom
Economic and Social Research Council. Helpful comments from Mike Clements, Jurgen Doornik, Neil
Ericsson, Bronwyn Hall, Grayham Mizon, John Muellbauer, Danny Quah and an anonymous referee are
gratefully acknowledged. The paper is closely based on Hendry (I 993) and draws heavily on Hendry (I 995)
as background, and Hendry and Morgan (I995) for historical context.
[ I622 ]

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.139 on Mon, 04 Apr 2016 22:07:26 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

[NOV. I995] ECONOMETRICS AND BUSINESS CYCLE I623

data-based methodology induces sample dependence of models, namely, results


which vary across different samples.
Thirdly, concerning economic theory, it can deliver important insights into

how an economic system might function, enhanced by the fact that we are also
agents. This should not be extrapolated to the belief that theory is 'correct'
since in practice, economic theories are seriously incomplete, highly aggregate,

make demanding assumptions about economic agents, rely on an unstated

multitude of ceteris paribus assumptions, change over time, and co-exist with
rival explanations. Thus, no firm theoretical basis exists either: that arm-chair
theoretical deduction could be claimed to tell us more about reality than
empirical study is a relic of a failed scholasticism. No matter how good
economic theory may be, it is manifestly inadequate to characterise many
salient aspects of real-world economies. An overemphasis on theory, which at
the extreme involves imposing the theory model on data, leads to the theory
dependence of results, where the very relevance of empirical evidence changes as
theory progresses.

All models - theory or empirical - are not born equal, and economics needs
those which are useful for understanding economic behaviour, for testing

economic theories, for forecasting, and for analysing economic policy. All four
objectives involve discovering sustainable empirical relationships between

observed economic magnitudes, and rejecting models which lack desirable


characteristics. This viewpoint directs the subsequent analysis. Since the

economy is too large and complicated to sustain 'true' models, empirical


models are invariably simplifications and, in that sense, inevitably false.
Consequently, we require other criteria than truth to judge empirical models.

This formulation and its related concepts are discussed in Hendry (I995). The
two main concepts used below are congruence and encompassing. The former
denotes that the empirical model matches the available evidence in all
measured attributes (e.g. is consistent with the theory from which it was
ostensibly derived, with unexplained components that are innovations against
available information, and parameters that are constant when assumed so,
etc.). The latter denotes that the model of interest can account for the results
of rival models of the same phenomena (see Mizon and Richard, I986).
Congruent, encompassing models need not be 'true' in any sense.

My experience is that economic theory and econometrics combine fruitfully


and produce more than either individually, highlighting the advantages of a
joint approach. Either could be used in isolation, but if used alone is shown

below to have drawbacks as part of a process of accumulating knowledge about


economic behaviour: substantive progress only seems likely from a combined
approach. That conclusion, however, does not resolve the issues of what theory,
what evidence, and how they are to be combined.

The structure of the paper is as follows. We first comment on the potential


role of economic theory, then consider any likely precedence of theory or

evidence in general. Since structure is central to the sustainability of economic


relations, Section III defines it as invariance under extensions of the
information set over time, across regimes, and for new sources. The main result
? Royal Economic Society I995

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.139 on Mon, 04 Apr 2016 22:07:26 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

i624

THE

ECONOMIC

JOURNAL

[NOVEMBER

is that partial knowledge of structure can be acquired empirically without prior


omniscience, whereas theory alone cannot deliver structure in principle.
Section IV considers the problems of theory dependence and sample
dependence when data modelling by econometric methods, against the

background that empirical evidence is essential to distinguish between rival


theoretical views. Finally, Section V examines the extent to which alternative
modelling approaches are likely to lead to the discovery of structure. It shows

that some approaches fail to determine structure on one or more of its


requirements, so they cannot offer a viable route for structural econometrics.
In particular, calibration may lose insights gleaned from the theory, and is

subject to potentially serious problems of both theory dependence and sample


dependence. However, other econometric approaches could yield aspects of
economic structure.
I. ECONOMIC THEORY

The positive arguments for basing empirical research on economic analysis are
powerful. First, the principles of economic theory are nearly independent of the

specific phenomena to be explained as they rely on assumptions about latent


propensities of economic agents (e.g. individualistic utility maximisers). What
could have been a weakness has proved to be a strength, since ad hoc arguments
infrequently hold sway, and most economic analyses are recognisably similar in
broad outline, have clear commonalties, and rarely represent a sequence of
disparate analyses. Although the same principles apply to many empirical
problems, crucial details differ including what function is maximised, what its
arguments are, what constraints operate, and what information is used.

Further, institutional frameworks can play a key role. Whether economic


incentives operate is not contentious, but the 'detailed' issues are precisely why
empirical evidence is essential to make our science operational. For example,
tastes and technology may not prove to be a useful basis for 'structural' analysis
due to their endogenous responses to other economic factors.
Secondly, 'explanations' by economic theory could apply despite there

being no quantitative laws (see Robbins, I932), although the absence of any
evidence may render the concept of 'explanation' empty. Even so, one could
imagine a world where price and quantity were never reliably related, yet
'laws' of supply and demand operated. However, this positive argument for
theory only becomes a negative one for econometrics with the unsubstantiated
claim that useful empirical regularities do not exist.
Thirdly, economic analysis has a perceived general success in explaining
economic behaviour, from why the postman delivers our mail, through why
health care is hard to deliver effectively, to why the 'Oil crisis' would not end
economic growth. However, some issues have not yielded, one of the most
salient being high levels of unemployment in OECD countries. Moreover, the

success is a 'broad sweep' explanation, not always accompanied by precise and


accurate quantitative statements about magnitudes, speeds of adjustment to
change etc. This is exactly the basis on which econometrics was founded.
Finally, economic concepts and models are an essential component of our
? Royal Economic Society I995

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.139 on Mon, 04 Apr 2016 22:07:26 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

I995] ECONOMETRICS AND BUSINESS CYCLE i625

cognitive structure, and it is difficult to think about economic events without


invoking aspects of existing theory. The consistency and generality of economic

theory endow it with considerable power as a first-order description of


individual economic behaviour in relatively static circumstances. However,

theories are drastic abstractions which focus on only a few phenomena in


isolation from other potential influences. Even at their best, they are incomplete

and idealised descriptions. Notwithstanding the rhetoric of the real business


cycle (RBC) literature, there is a large gap between an abstract theory of an
unrationed, inter-temporal optimising agent and an empirical model of
aggregate behaviour. Other sources of information and forms of reasoning than
just economic theory are obviously admissible in formulating and analysing
parameters of interest: theory needs to be used flexibly to guide an analysis
rather than be simply imposed on data.

II. PRECEDENCE OF THEORY OR EVIDENCE

Whether theoretical advances lead or follow empirical discoveries depends

partly on the quality of, and pre-eminence accorded to, theory: both orderings
occur in practice. Since new contributions can affect all existing knowledge in
an empirical science, neither can claim logical precedence. Substantive

reconstructions of any aspect can overturn the existing edifice. Nevertheless,


granted an insistence on progression, neither contradictory empirical evidence,
nor new theories, alone will reject the status quo. Empirical anomalies may act

as prompts for discovery, but the only available theory will almost never be

rejected by adverse evidence alone: a better alternative is needed to sustain the


scientific goal of progressive understanding. Similarly, new theories may lead
to questioning the status of previous evidence, and often stimulate a search for

new findings, but 'protection' strategies also exist, so haphazard progress, or

even degeneration, can result. In any case, the rejection of an empirical model
does not entail rejecting the theory from which it was derived, nor does
corroborating the model entail the validity of the theory (Section V considers
testing rival theories in econometrics).

Further, theory is neither necessary nor sufficient for successful policy


intervention. Necessity is refuted by a counter example from biochemistry:

aspirin is perhaps the most common scientific intervention in everyday life as


a pain killer, but until recently there was no rigorous theory as to how it

worked. This did not stop aspirin from working (the initial use of aspirin acetylsalicylic acid - arose as a folklore remedy for hangovers, based on
brewing willow-tree bark, of which it is a natural constituent: see Weissmann,
I99I). Sufficiency falls on the example of a theory that is violently false, such
as that a huge dose of arsenic will cure a cold with no side effects.

Three famous earlier debates concerned with whether to acquire economic


knowledge from directly analysing phenomena or from 'fundamental theory'
in the context of business cycle analysis are extensively discussed in Hendry and
Morgan (I995) (see Moore, I9I4, versus Wright, I9I5; Keynes, I939, versus

Tinbergen, I940; and Koopmans, I947, versus Vining, I949). The outcomes
? Royal Economic Society I995

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.139 on Mon, 04 Apr 2016 22:07:26 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

I626 THE ECONOMIC JOURNAL [NOVEMBER


served to emphasise the dangers of relying on either theory or evidence in
isolation. Even though the third debate ended as one of research priority, rather
than of the principle of using economic theory and statistical methods in
analysing economic data, a dominant theme of econometrics since then has

been studying empirical models through pre-specified theoretical models. The


RBC literature is an extreme example thereof.

III. STRUCTURE

Structure has many meanings in econometrics (see, inter alia, the different

notions in Frisch (I 934), Haavelmo (I 944), Wold and Jureen (I 953), Bardsen
and Fisher (I 993), and Juselius (I 993), as well as connoting 'being derived
from inter-temporal optimisation by economic agents'). Here, we define
structure as the set of invariant features of the economic mechanism. This

captures the idea of permanence in a framework which is hidden from direct


view and needs to be uncovered. The parameters of an economic structure may
include those of agents' decision rules, but there is no presumption that these

must be derived by inter-temporal optimisation (particularly by a so-called


'representative agent'). Then, e0 defines a structure if it is invariant and
directly characterises the relations of the economy under analysis. Thus,
structure need not be identifiable, and correspondences between model and
reality are not fully testable. However, an immediate consequence of the

definition is that a parameter can be structural only if it is invariant to an


extension of the sample period (constant), invariant to changes elsewhere in the
economy (regime shifts), and invariant to extensions of the information set
(adding more variables): all three of these aspects are open to empirical

scrutiny, so necessary attributes of structure are testable even if sufficient ones


are not.

IV. THEORY DEPENDENCE VERSUS SAMPLE DEPENDENCE

There are many extant approaches in empirical economics and we consider a

caricature of three of these. Theory dependence is construed as the problem


that the 'empirical' results are merely a quantified theory model and are

therefore no more or less valid than the initial theory; sample dependence is the
opposite extreme that the results are subject to important sampling vagaries.
A. Theory-driven Approaches

The RBC approach starts with a theoretical model and estimates (or
calibrates) its parameters; deliberately little testing is done on any one
occasion, and little is learnt from the data. Between occasions, however, the
theory is revised in the light of manifest failures, then reapplied to (essentially)
the same data, inducing a sophisticated data-mining problem. Such 'theory-

driven' approaches, where a model is derived from a priori theory and calibrated
from data evidence, suffer from theory dependence. Their credibility depends
on the credibility of the theory from which they arose, and when that theory
C Royal Economic Society I995

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.139 on Mon, 04 Apr 2016 22:07:26 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

I995] ECONOMETRICS AND BUSINESS CYCLE I627

is discarded, so is the associated evidence (see Kydland and Prescott, I 99 I). Since
economic theory is progressing rapidly, theory dependence is likely to induce
transient and non-structural evidence.
If an empirical implementation is discarded when it is inconsistent with the
theory, the theory loses credibility, whereas if the implementation is not

discarded, the theory must be altered to avoid maintaining contradictory


propositions. Of course, the phenomena that induced 'rejection' may be
unrelated to the ostensible nature of the problem: for example, the
measurement process may be at fault. Evidence that this is so must be adduced
to 'rescue' the theory model. In practice, the empirical model, the

measurement instruments, and the theory may be revised till consistency is


achieved. Depending on how model design is implemented, the result may or

may not lack credibility. But postulating an endless sequence of theories that
get rejected in turn fails to incorporate learning from the evidence. My
proposed solution is to conduct research in a progressive framework of

successively encompassing, congruent models consolidated by empirically


relevant theories.
As an aside, so-called 'stylised facts' seem to denote abstracted summary

statistics of aspects of marginal distributions. A set of stylised facts may be a


reasonable summary of the salient features of each element of the data taken in

isolation (e.g. an output growth rate of 2-5%, a savings rate of io%, a real

interest rate of 400, and an unemployment rate of 80%), yet jointly can be
inconsistent with the evidence in that there is a negligible probability of

observing the vector of claimed stylised facts, given the joint distribution of the
original data. There seem no good reasons for eschewing internally consistent

multivariate estimates- and avoiding rejection of poor empirical models is a

bad reason. However, recent work suggests some convergence of 'estimation'


approaches, and indeed models: see Burnside and Eichenbaum (I 994) and

Watson (I 993) .
By ignoring the possibility that the claimed 'parameters' of RBC models

may not in fact be constant, existing calibration approaches, matching a subset


of data moments, induce a perverse sample-dependence problem - for the very
models that apparently strive to avoid this difficulty. If any of the parameters
are non-constant, then the values used are dependent on the particular sample
or historical epoch chosen, and will vary as the period changes: the estimated
model then suffers from both theory dependence and sample dependence.
B. Data-driven Approaches

An alternative approach abandons structural modelling, and estimates data-

descriptive models such as ARIMAs or VARs. 'Data-driven' approaches,


where models are developed to closely describe the data, may suffer from
sample dependence in that accidental and transient data features are embodied
as tightly in the model as permanent aspects, so that extensions of the data set

may reveal predictive failure. Restrictions are sometimes imposed to offset this
problem. These could be data-based as in Box and Jenkins (I976) modelling

with its 'identification' procedures, or claim an extraneous source as in the


C Royal Economic Society I995

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.139 on Mon, 04 Apr 2016 22:07:26 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

I628

THE

ECONOMIC

JOURNAL

[NOVEMBER

'Minnesota prior' which shrinks lagged dependent variable parameters to


unity and others to zero (see Doan et al. I984). However, such restrictions will

deliver structure only if the resulting parameters chance to coincide with


invariant aspects of the underlying relations (even so, such restrictions could
improve forecasting: see Clements and Hendry, I994).
Empirical models which are not quantitative facsimiles of theory models are
sometimes dismissed as the outcome of 'data mining'. This phrase connotes a

prejudiced search for corroborative evidence (see Leamer, I978), and may
even be believed to vitiate any substantive role for empirical evidence in

economics. Since models can be designed to satisfy selection criteria, we must


distinguish that legitimate productive activity from one of 'torturing data till
a false confession is obtained'. Following Gilbert (1 986), distinguish weak data

mining, whereby corroboration is sought for a prior belief, from strong data
mining, in which conflicting evidence is either camouflaged or not reported. A
model-search process which deliberately camouflages conflicting results is
unscientific, but is open to adversarial scrutiny by seeing how well the resulting
model accounts for the findings of rival studies. Thus, the resolution of potential
data-mining criticisms is to explain the Gestalt of empirical evidence: strong
data mining fails when there is already conflicting evidence; weak data mining
fails when other models cannot be emcompassed.
C. Data Modelling Using Economic Theory Guidelines
A further approach attempts to merge inference from data with guidelines from
economic theory, emphasising empirical models as reductions which can be
designed to be congruent. Cointegration analysis, seeking to establish robust

conclusions about long-run relations between integrated (usually I ( i))


variables, has been extensively adopted in this approach, but is by no means
restricted to it. Relative to the previous extremes, this approach seeks to
characterise data parsimoniously in a general economic theoretical framework,

as well as providing a statistical baseline against,which other models can be


evaluated (see Spanos, I990).

Simplification procedures are often used in data modelling, and these could
attenuate or exacerbate sample dependence: the former by eliminating

irrelevant factors, the latter if the influences of accidental aspects are captured
more 'significantly'. This last difficulty may be offset by reference to a theory
model, but is a transient problem since an extended data sample will reveal the
accidental nature of the earlier effects by their becoming less significant.

Such an approach also often relies on multiple tests. A misplaced objection

to statistical testing is that test statistics can be made insignificant by


construction. Selecting an empirical model to ensure that a test criterion is
insignificant guarantees such a outcome - independently of the correctness of
the solution. Some of the worries about 'data mining' may arise because tests
can be made insignificant by iteratively revising models in the light of adverse
data evidence. Certainly, model design strategies can lead to the misinterpretation of diagnostic tests, so a clear reporting distinction is needed
between tests which are used as within-sample model-design criteria (reflecting
K Royal Economic Society I995

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.139 on Mon, 04 Apr 2016 22:07:26 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

I995] ECONOMETRICS AND BUSINESS CYCLE I629

the exploitation of data evidence), and genuine tests in the Neyman-Pearson


sense (using previously unavailable evidence). Even so, rejection on any test
entails model invalidity or a type I error. While multiple testing may raise
worries about 'pre-test' problems, not doing so ignores the opposite problem
of never discovering that the model class is incorrect (see Mayo, I98I). The
analysis in White (I990) shows that testing provides one strategy for ensuring
the selection of an acceptable data representation, providing the significance

level of the complete testing process is controlled and declines as the sample
grows.
Rejecting a null hypothesis against a specific hypothesis provides no
information about an appropriate alternative model. This is a minor variant of
the Duhem-Quine thesis (see Cross, I982), which also reveals that rejecting an

empirical model does not entail rejecting the theory from which it was derived,
nor does accepting .the model entail the validity of the theory: mutually
incompatible congruent empirical models can be designed to match in-

consistent theories (see Mizon, I993). Although most empirical testing is to


ascertain the status of assumptions behind empirical models, not to test
theories, the latter is feasible since incompatible congruent empirical models
cannot mutually encompass each other.
D. Overview

All three approaches base their conclusions on a mixture of theory and


evidence, but accord very different weights to the components, and often have
very different constructions of admissible theory. These major differences in
approach reflect genuine difficulties in empirical economics and are not merely

fads. There are obvious dangers in trying to learn more from a relatively short,
autocorrelated, non-homogeneous, non-stationary, imprecise and inaccurate
data sample than it can reasonably yield. The problem of sample dependence
of findings is especially acute in practice because all aspects of an empirical
model may be designed to satisfy pre-assigned criteria, even parameter

constancy (highlighting the distinction between explanation and prediction:


see Hendry and Starr, I993). Conversely, the ability of pure theory to deliver
ideas about permanent relationships is far from established. Since congruent

and invariant models depend on the identification of structural relations, the


major issue remains the respective weight to be accorded to avoiding theory
dependence and sample dependence of econometric evidence. Good empirical
modelling helps mitigate the sample dependence of findings while linking
evidence to theory.

V. DETERMINING STRUCTURE IN PRACTICE

Economies are subject to regime shifts as well as technological and financial


innovations which force adaptation and learning by economic agents, and
induce different forms of non-stationarity. Empirical studies in econometrics
are limited in scope over time and information sets, comprising a small set of
variables relative to the potentially important determinants of any economic
K Royal Economic Society I995

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.139 on Mon, 04 Apr 2016 22:07:26 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

i630

THE

ECONOMIC

JOURNAL

[NOVEMBER

phenomena. Thus, it is unsurprising that our evidence is less secure than in


natural sciences, a difficulty exacerbated by the minuscule resources allocated
to data collection in economics.
Important and unresolved issues of principle in econometrics are whether
structure exists, and if so, whether it can be 'identified' in any sense. As implied

by our framework, when structure exists it could be determined in a progressive


research strategy: partial knowledge of structure may be acquired without

complete knowledge in advance of what structure comprises. Without such a


result, structural knowledge could not be acquired till everything was known,

contradicting the realised progress of science. However, identification has three


other attributes: 'uniqueness', 'correspondence to the desired entity' and
'satisfying the assumed interpretation'. For example, a regression of quantity
on price delivers a unique function of the data second moments, but need not

correspond to any underlying demand behaviour, and may be incorrectly


interpreted as a supply schedule. Koopmans et al. (I950) formalised conditions
for the uniqueness of coefficients in simultaneous systems, often the sense

intended in econometrics, but conditions for the correspondence of model

parameters to those of DGPs, or for the correct interpretation of parameters,


are not easily specified. In practice, the meaning of 'identified' can be
ambiguous as in 'Have you identified the parameters of the money demand
function?'.

The logic of our analysis is perhaps best seen by applying it to five aspects
of econometric modelling. Each of these either offers what I deem to be
achievable conditions for structure to be determined, or highlights the
drawbacks of approaches that seem unlikely to achieve structural knowledge.

A. Identified Cointegration Vectors


Given an information set {xt}, where xt is n x i, consider the cointegrated VAR:
h-1

Axt = Ai Axt-i + al}Xt_h + ut where ut - IN. [o, ], (I)


where oc and P are n x r matrices of feedback and cointegrating coefficients
respectively (see Johansen, I 988, Phillips, i 99 i, and Banerjee et al., I 993). Even
assuming that (i) captures the long-run dependencies, any coordinate system
is acceptable for the cointegration space without further restrictions, since

e4i' _ aPP-l,' = e*p*'. Unless sufficient valid identifying restrictions are


imposed, the set of cointegrating vectors will not correspond to a structural
relation, and need not be interpretable in the light of theory. When the

empirical analysis yields oc*p*' instead of o4p', let the first vector be *' xt_ =
ft1 Xl + P2 xt-1. This has two consequences. First, by using PI* xt-, rather than

pj xt_, the unwanted I(o) combination Pjxt_ makes the resulting equation

non-structural. Secondly, if PJ xt_ enters any other equation, weak exogeneity


will be violated with adverse implications for inference (see Engle et al. I983,
and Hendry, I 994) .

Conversely, consider the cointegrating matrix P once sufficient valid


restrictions have been imposed to ensure unique identification, such that the
X Royal Economic Society I995

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.139 on Mon, 04 Apr 2016 22:07:26 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

I995] ECONOMETRICS AND BUSINESS CYCLE I631

resulting characterisation of the long run matches that of the DGP and is
constant over prolonged periods of time. Then , would constitute structural

knowledge. To identify the structural cointegration vectors J8 certainly


necessitates both careful formulation of the long-run economic analysis and
thorough testing of the requisite restrictions. Johansen and Juselius (I992)
show the latter aspect in operation, and Hendry and Mizon (I993) investigate
the former. However, once an identifiable , is determined, it is unique under

expansions of the information set. This follows because I'xt is I(o), so once J is
identifiable then that is not affected by the presence of additional variables,
whether these are I(o) or I(i) (cointegrated or not).
In a linear system, , is an invariant, and cointegration could be defined by

that property. Premultiply (i) by any non-singular n x n matrix Q:


h-1

QAAxt = -i At Ax + QxP'Xt-h + tu*


i=l

The adjustment coefficients are altered to Qx, whereas J'xt remain the
cointegrating vectors. This result extends to 1(2) processes, and to conditional

models of yt given zt when xt = (Yt: zt) (the transformation E12 21 only affects
a). As Ericsson et al. (I994) show, P is also invariant to seasonal adjustment
filters like XI I. We conclude that identified P represent one aspect of structure
that may be determinable without omniscience.
B. Orthogonal Parameters

A second example is a linear conditional model with parameters which are


super exogenous on variables which are both mutually orthogonal and are
orthogonal to excluded functions of information. Extending the information set
over time, across regime shifts or by additional variables will not alter the
knowledge achieved: being invariant and constant, such parameters satisfy all
the testable attributes of structurality. This situation may arise when economic
agents orthogonalise information in their decision rules, in which case, the
entailed model could capture structural information. Meta-considerations

would be needed to decide whether the parameters in fact correspond to the


actual hidden structure. I do not claim that the world must satisfy the
assumptions needed to sustain the existence of such a structure, merely that
when it does so, a suitable progressive research strategy may acquire empirical
knowledge without complete prior information as to the nature of that
structure. The point is one of principle: regression parameters could embody
structure. In practice, conditional models with nearly orthogonal parameters
have proved surprisingly durable and robust. An example is provided by the
long sequence of studies on the UK consumption function from Davidson et al.
(I 978) through Hendry et al. (I990) to Muellbauer and Murphy (I 993) and

Harvey and Scott (I 993): the original dynamic and 'error-correction'


parameters recur in greatly extended information sets and over longer time
periods, despite considerable regime shifts. This is one answer to Eichenbaum's

question about the importance of such parameters. Another answer is that a


K Royal Economic Society I995

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.139 on Mon, 04 Apr 2016 22:07:26 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

i632

THE

ECONOMIC

JOURNAL

[NOVEMBER

value of zero for the error-correction term may entail non-stationarity,


affecting inference, as well as the presence of cointegrating structure.

By way of contrast, other features sometimes emphasised in modelling seem


to need an additional assumption of omniscience to justify a claim to
structurality. We consider two examples.
C. Inappropriate Estimation

Perhaps the greatest worry from using 'inconsistent' estimators is that they
deliver different parameters in the empirical model from those which would
have been obtained by more appropriate methods. Consequently, structure
could be lost despite a clever prior analysis. For example, as Campos et al.
(I996) show, if the two-step method in Engle and Granger (I987) is used when
the imposed common factor restrictions are invalid (see Kremers et al., I992),

breaks in marginal distributions are carried into the procedure, so structurality


can be lost in the model despite its presence in reality. Thus, the operating
characteristics of our tools merit careful analysis to ensure that econometric

procedures do not lose hard-earned insights.


Since so-called 'calibration' methods have been subjected to little formal

analysis, and what exists is rather critical (see Canova et al., I992, Kim and
Pagan, I993, and Hoover, I995), one must be concerned that implementations
of the resulting models could be non-structural even when the theory happened
to capture some structural aspects of reality. Worse still, present intertemporal
optimisation theory seems ineffective without arbitrary assumptions about
stochastic forcing functions (such as technical progress) which do not themselves
have a theory basis as yet.
D. Residual Analysis

A similar difficulty plagues attempts to interpret residuals on econometric

equations, such as for impulse-response analysis (see Sims, I 980), or for


correspondence of residuals to 'supply' or 'demand' shocks (see Blanchard and
Quah, I989). A model could embody (partial) structure in its parameters yet
have non-structural errors: Section B provided an example. Focusing on the

unmodelled component in an analysis seems unlikely to be as productive as


seeking to interpret what has been explicitly modelled.
A more mixed possibility arises in a fifth example.

E. Expectations and Structure


A theory, or class of models (rather than just a single exemplar), could be
rejected by testing against a class of encompassing contenders which are mutual
counter examples: see Favero and Hendry (I 992) who use an idea proposed in
Boland (i 989). For example, the Lucas (I 976) critique leads to an expectations'
based counter example to any claimed invariant conditional model. However,
the converse also holds, so a 'crucial' test between them is feasible: there
are automatically two mutually inconsistent theories when expectations are

involved (namely, feedback and feedforward models: see Hendry, I 988). When
no member of one class can encompass a congruent representative of the other,
? Royal Economic Society I995

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.139 on Mon, 04 Apr 2016 22:07:26 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

I995] ECONOMETRICS AND BUSINESS CYCLE I633

then that class is in grave doubt. If agents form expectations about zt when
planning Yt, then behavioural parameters +1 will depend on the expectations
parameters +2 of the zt process, and should alter when +2 changes. This is a
testable hypothesis, with the implication that the failure of +1 to change when
+2 changes is inconsistent with the critique.
Since both conditional and expectational models can be derived from the

sequential joint density of (Yt: zt), and all sensible forms of expectations should
be cointegrated with outcomes, aspects of the Lucas critique are testable in a
framework of cointegration where some of the expectations variables are

subject to regime shifts (see Hendry and Neale, I988). The constancy of a
conditional model in the face of a changing marginal process entails that agents
do not use expectations models to predict future values of relevant decision
variables. A possible explanation is that contingent planning dominates
forward-looking behaviour in practice. Another possibility is that agents form
expectations without using models, but use data-based predictors, perhaps
because of high costs of information collection and processing (especially the

difficulty of discovering a usable approximation to the DGP when it is subject


to intermittent regime shifts!). The detailed analysis in Ericsson and Irons
(I996) suggests that almost no test of the critique has ever rejected the
conditional model, whereas several results are inconsistent with the critique.
We conclude that the possible role of expectations in agent behaviour does
not preclude learning about structure from data evidence.

VI. CONCLUSION

The development of congruent, theory-consistent, and encompassing models


remains a viable route in econometrics, even with non-stationary data. When
structure represents an invariant feature of reality, progressive research can

discover it in part without prior knowledge of the whole: Keynes's worry about
the prior necessity of a complete specification is misplaced. Tests for necessary
attributes of structure exist, especially its invariance to extensions of the
information over longer time periods (constancy), regime changes (parameter

invariance, or super exogeneity in conditional models), or additional sources of


variation (added variables). Even though empirical models are perforce
reductions of the data generation process, and can be explicitly designed to

satisfy various criteria, they can embody structure. Conversely, an emphasis on


interpreting the unmodelled component in a model seems misplaced, as
'errors ' could be structural only with the additional assumption of omniscience.
A key property of economic analysis is to delineate the economic structure,

but by itself, it cannot endow a parameter with structurality since the mapping
involved is between a theory and a model, whereas structure concerns a
mapping between a model and reality. The best is that theory delivers a model

which happens to capture structure after appropriate estimation. Since


structure must be invariant under extensions of the information set, it cannot
be learnt from theory alone without an assumption of omniscience. However,
? Royal Economic Society I995

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.139 on Mon, 04 Apr 2016 22:07:26 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

I634

THE

ECONOMIC

JOURNAL

[NOVEMBER

structure potentially can be learned from empirical evidence without prior


knowledge as to what exists to be discovered. Hence, economic theory is neither
necessary nor sufficient for determining structure, although it remains one of

several useful tools for the econometrician.

Nevertheless, economic theory is likely to prove a productive companion in


empirical econometric research, by suggesting directions for discovering
structure, excluding unlikely contenders, helping identify structure (in all three
senses of uniqueness, correspondence and interpretation), and consolidating

empirical findings. Theoretical reasoning is of considerable help in determining


parameters of interest, although how one discovers useful knowledge remains
an art rather than a science. But good econometric modelling practice is also
important if structure is not to be lost from inappropriate procedures. The
negative reasons for using economic theory have less force than is sometimes

argued, in that best practice does not fall foul of them, even if there remain
potential problems due to moral hazard (selecting only a favourable subset of

results to report, etc.). The positive aspects of theory provide a much stronger

case without resolving what are the precise theories of relevance and how best
to use them. Finally, the two-way interaction between evidence and theory
would benefit from being strengthened in practice.
Nuffield College, Oxford
REFERENCES

Banerjee, A., Dolado, J. J., Galbraith, J. W. and Hendry, D. F. (I 993). Co-integration, Error Correction and the
Econometric Analysis of Non-Stationary Data. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Bardsen, G. and Fisher, P. G. (I993). 'The importance of being structured.' Discussion paper, Norwegian
School of Economics, Bergen.

Blanchard, 0. and Quah, D. (i 989). 'The dynamic effects of aggregate demand and supply disturbances.'
American Economic Reiew, vol. 79, pp. 655-73.
Boland, L. A. (I989). The Methodology of Economic Model Building. London: Routledge.

Box, G. E. P. and Jenkins, G. M. (1976). Time Series Analysis, Forecasting and Control. San Francisco:
Holden-Day.
Burnside, C. and Eichenbaum, M. (1994). 'Factor hoarding and the business cycle.' Mimeo, Economic
department, University of Pittsburgh.
Campos, J., Ericsson, N. R. and Hendry, D. F. (I996). 'Cointegration tests in the presence of structural
breaks.' Journal of Econometrics, in press.
Canova, F., Finn, M. and Pagan, A. R. (I992). 'Evaluating a real business cycle model.' Discussion paper,
Australian National University.

Clements, M. P. and Hendry, D. F. (I994). 'Intercept corrections and structural change.' Mimeo, Institute
of Economics and Statistics, University of Oxford.
Cross, R. (I982). 'The Duhem-Quine thesis, Lakatos and the appraisal of theories in macro-economics.'
ECONOMIC JOURNAL, vol. 92, pp. 320-40.

Davidson, J. E. H., Hendry, D. F., Srba, F. and Yeo, S. (I978). 'Econometric modelling of the aggregate
time-series relationship between consumers' expenditure and income in the United Kingdom.'

ECONOMIC JOURNAL, vol. 88, pp. 661-92. Reprinted in Hendry, D. F. (I993), Econometrics: Alchemy or
Science? Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.

Doan, T., Litterman, R. and Sims, C. A. (I984). 'Forecasting and conditional projection using realistic prior
distributions.' Econometric Reviews, vol. 3, pp. I-ioo.
Engle, R F. and Granger, C. W. J. (I987). 'Cointegration and error correction: representation, estimation

and testing.' Econometrica, vol. 55, pp. 25I-76.


Engle, R. F., Hendry, D. F. and Richard, J.-F. (I983). 'Exogeneity.' Econometrica, vol. 51, pp. 277-304.

Reprinted in Hendry, D. F. (993), Econometrics: Alchemy or Science? Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.


Ericsson, N. R., Hendry, D. F. and Tran, H.-A. (I994). 'Cointegration, seasonality, encompassing and the
demand for money in the United Kingdom.' In Non-stationary Time-series Analyses and Cointegration (ed.
C. Hargreaves), pp. I79-224. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

( Royal Economic Society I995

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.139 on Mon, 04 Apr 2016 22:07:26 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

I995] ECONOMETRICS AND BUSINESS CYCLE I635


Ericsson, N. R. and Irons, J. S. (i996). 'The Lucas critique in practice: theory without measurement.' In
Macroeconometrics: Developments, Tensions and Prospects (ed. K. D. Hoover). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic
Press. Forthcoming.

Favero, C. and Hendry, D. F. (I 992). 'Testing the Lucas critique: a review.' Econometric Reviews, vol. I I, pp.
265-306.

Frisch, R. (I 934). Statistical Confluence Analysis by Means of Complete Regression Systems. Oslo: University Institute
of Economics.

Gilbert, C. L. (i986). 'Professor Hendry's methodology.' Oxford Bulletin of Economics and Statistics, vol. 48, pp.

283-307. Reprinted in Modelling Economic Series (ed. C. W. J. Granger, I990), Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Haavelmo, T. (I944). 'The probability approach in econometrics.' Econometrica, vol. I2, pp. I-ii8.
Supplement.

Harvey, A. C. and Scott, A. (I993). 'Seasonality in dynamic regression models.' Unpublished paper,
London School of Economics.

Hendry, D. F. (I988). 'The encompassing implications of feedback versus feedforward mechanisms in


econometrics.' Oxford Economic Papers, vol. 40, pp. I32-49.
Hendry, D. F. (I993). 'The roles of economic theory and econometrics in time-series economics.' Invited
address, European Econometric Society, Uppsala.

Hendry, D. F. (I 994) . 'On the interactions of unit roots and exogeneity.' Econometric Reviews. (forthcoming).

Hendry, D. F. (I995). Dynamic Econometrics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.


Hendry, D. F. and Mizon, G. E. (I993). 'Evaluating dynamic econometric models by encompassing the

VAR.' In Models, Methods and Applications of Econometrics (ed. P. C. B. Phillips), pp. 272-300. Oxford:
Basil Blackwell.

Hendry, D. F. and Morgan, M. S. (I 995). The Foundations of Econometric Analysis. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.

Hendry, D. F., Muellbauer, J. N. J. and Murphy, T. A. (i 990). 'The econometrics of DHSY.' In A Century
of Economics (ed. J. D. Hey and D. Winch), pp. 298-334. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Hendry, D. F. and Neale, A. J. (I988). 'Interpreting long-run equilibrium solutions in conventional macro
models: a comment.' EcoNoMIc JOURNAL, vol. 98, pp. 8o8-I 7.

Hendry, D. F. and Starr, R. M. (I993). 'The demand for MI in the USA: a reply to James M. Boughton.'
ECONOMIC JOURNAL, vol. I03, pp. I 58-69.

Hoover, K. D. (1995). 'Facts and artifacts: calibration and the empirical assessment of real business cycle
models.' Oxford Economic Papers, vol. 47, pp. 24-44.
Johansen, S. (I988). 'Statistical analysis of cointegration vectors.' Journal of Economic Dynamics and Control,
vol. I2, pp. 23 I-54.

Joh-ansen, S. and Juselius, K. (I992). 'Testing structural hypotheses in a multivariate cointegration analysis
of the PPP and the UIP for UK.' Journal of Econometrics, vol. 53, pp.2I I-44.

Juselius, K. (I933). 'VAR modelling and Haavelmo's probability approach to econometrics.' Discussion
paper 9305, University of Copenhagen.

Keynes, J. M. (I939). 'Professor Tinbergen's method.' EcoNoMIc JOURNAL, vol. 44, pp. 558-68.
Kim, K. and Pagan, A. R. (I993). 'The econometric analysis of calibrated macroeconomic models.'
Discussion paper, Australian National University.

Koopmans, T. C. (I947). 'Measurement without theory.' Review of Economics and Statistics, vol. 29,
pp. I61-79.

Koopmans, T. C., Rubin, H. and Leipnik, R. B. (I950). 'Measuring the equation systems of dynamic
economics.' In Statistical Inference in Dynamic Economic Models (ed. T. C. Koopmans), No. I0 in Cowles
Commission Monograph, Ch. 2, New York: John Wiley & Sons.
Kremers,J.J. M., Ericsson, N. R. and Dolado,J. J. (I992). 'The power of cointegration tests.' Oxford Bulletin
of Economics and Statistics, vol. 54, pp. 325-48.
Kydland, F. E. and Prescott, E. C. (i99i). 'The econometrics of the general equilibrium approach to
business cycles.' Scandinavian Journal of Economics, vol. 93, pp. I6I-78.

Leamer, E. E. (1978). Specification Searches. Ad-Hoc Inference with Non-Experimental Data. New York: John
Wiley.

Lucas, R. E. (I 976). 'Econometric policy evaluation: A critique.' In The Phillips Curve and Labor Markets, vol.

I of Carnegie-Rochester Conferences on Public Policy (ed. K. Brunner and A. Meltzer), pp. I9-46.
Amsterdam: North-Holland Publishing Company.

Mayo, D. (i98i). 'Testing statistical testing.' In Philosophy in Economics, (ed. J. C. Pitt), pp. I75-230. D.

Reidel Publishing Co. Reprinted as pp. 45-73 in Caldwell, B. J. (I993), The Philosophy and Methodology

of Economics, vol. 2. Aldershot: Edward Elgar.


Mizon, G. E. (I 993). 'Empirical analysis of time series: illustrations with simulated data.' In Advanced Lectures
in Quantitative Economics, vol. II (ed. A. de Zeeuw), pp. I84-205. New York: Academic Press.
Mizon, G. E. and Richard, J.-F. (i986). 'The encompassing principle and its application to non-nested
hypothesis tests.' Econometrica, vol. 54, pp. 657-78.
Moore, H. L. (I9I4). Economic Cycles - Their Law and Cause. New York: Macmillan.

? Royal Economic Society I995

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.139 on Mon, 04 Apr 2016 22:07:26 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

I636 THE ECONOMIC JOURNAL [NOVEMBER I995]

Muellbauer, J. N.J. and Murphy, A. (I993). 'Income expectations, wealth and demography in the UK
consumption function.' Unpublished paper, Nuffield College, Oxford.

Phillips, P. C. B. (i99i). 'Optimal inference in cointegrated systems.' Econometrica, vol. 59, pp. 283-306.

Robbins, L. (I932). An Essay on the Nature and Significance of Economic Science. London: Macmillan.

Sims, C. A. (I980). 'Macroeconomics and reality.' Econometrica, vol. 48, pp. I-48. Reprinted in (C. W. J.
Granger ed.) (1990), Modelling Economic Series. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Spanos, A. ( I990). 'Towards a unifying methodological framework for econometric modelling.' In Modelling
Economic Series, (ed. C. W. J. Granger), pp. 335-64. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Tinbergen, J. (I 940) . Statistical Testing of Business-Cycle Theories, vol. I: A Method and its application to Investment
Activity. Geneva: League of Nations.
Vining, R. (I949). 'Methodological issues in quantitative economics.' Review of Economics and Statistics,
vol. 3I, pp. 77-86.
Watson, W. M. (I993). 'Measures of fit for calibrated models.' Journal of Political Economy, vol. ioI,
pp. I OII-4I.

Weissmann, G. (i99i). 'Aspirin.' Scientific American, vol. 264, no. I, pp. 58-64.

White, H. (I990). 'A consistent model selection.' In Modelling Economic Series (ed. C. W. J. Granger),
pp. 369-83. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Wold, H. 0. A. and Jureen, L. (I953). Demand Analysis: A Study in Econometrics, 2nd edn. New York: John
Wiley.

Wright, P. G. (I9I5). 'Moore's economic cycles.' Quarterly Journal of Economics, vol. 29, pp. 63I-4I.

K Royal Economic Society I995

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.139 on Mon, 04 Apr 2016 22:07:26 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

You might also like