You are on page 1of 5

Psychol Stud

DOI 10.1007/s12646-010-0032-3

REFLECTIONS

Karl Popper, Psychology and Philosophy


Neelam Kumar

Received: 16 March 2010 / Accepted: 30 August 2010


# National Academy of Psychology (NAOP) India 2010

Abstract This paper intends to re-emphasize the relationship Karl Popper can be described as one of the most
among Psychology, Popper and his Philosophy. Popper, who important and widely known philosophers of science of
is often considered as one of the most important philosophers the twentieth century. Interestingly, the root of Popper’s
of science, had associations with the discipline of psychology philosophy of science has been traced to the psychology
in his early years. Popper was associated with Würzburg of the Wurzburg school, especially the psychologies of
school of psychology, especially the psychologies of Külpe, Selz and Bühler. Popper’s psychological arguments and
Selz and Bühler. However, there was a change in Popper’s data enabled him to develop his characteristic deductive
interest from the psychology of discovery to an objectivist stance in epistemology and philosophy of science.
epistemology—that is, to the logic of discovery, which he Popper, around 1929 or thereabouts, shifted his inquiry
himself acknowledged (1976, p. 55). Popper, not only turned from psychology to the logic of science. Popper himself
away from psychology, as early as 1930 or thereabouts, he acknowledges a change in his interest from the psychol-
later became one of the most outspoken opponents of a ogy of discovery (and thinking) to an objective episte-
psychological approach to science. This antipathy has worked mology—that is, to the logic of discovery (p. 55, 75).
both ways! Very few psychologists study and discuss Popper. This paper emphasizes that psychologists should not
His place in the history of psychology, certainly remains ignore Popper. The paper also intends to discuss why
inadequate. But why should psychologists ignore Popper? and how Popperian thinking shows marks of dismissal
Instead of turning away from Popper, Psychologists’ efforts for psychology in the science studies. The role of
should be directed towards bringing into focus Popper, his psychology within science studies is especially impor-
works and association with psychology. This paper argues and tant: a) as science constitutes one of the most important
tries to discuss the relationships among Popper, his training in domain related to human beings; and b) it has been
psychology and his philosophy. argued that behaviourism, as a revolution against
dualistic mentalism in psychology, was one of the three
Keywords Psychology of Science . Popper . Philosophy of forces whose convergence into a common effort resulted
Science . Kuhn . Boring . Külpe . Selz and Bühler in the emergence of Science of Science1 (Stevens 1939,
251).

Introduction
Popper and Psychology

Karl Popper started his career as a psychologist—wrote his


It is still not widely appreciated that Sir Karl Popper’s
Ph.D thesis on psychology of thinking. Shortly before
initial interest was psychology, not philosophy.
submitting his dissertation for his Ph.D., the focus of
Jacobs (1989, p, 173)

N. Kumar (*)
1
NISTADS, Operationalism as a revolution against absolute and undefinable
New Delhi, India concepts in physics, and Logical Positivism as a revolution against
e-mail: kumarneelam28@gmail.com rational metaphysics in philosophy were the other two forces.
Psychol Stud

Popper’s interest switched from the psychology, to the method of science and chose falsifiability as a criterion for
methodology, of thought and problem-solving, and in demarcating science from non-science. He made a distinction
particular to the methodology of science. Popper had between the context of discovery and context of justification.
studied both psychology and pedagogy. His intellectual He agreed with the consensus that the “context of discovery,”
interests led him to psychology while the professional which concerns with the origin of hypotheses, is properly a
ambitions led him to teaching and pedagogy. Popper matter for psychology. He regarded only the “context of
completed his doctorate under the supervision of psychol- justification” of concern to the epistemology of science.
ogist Karl Buhler (Kurz 1996). His problem grew out of his Popper charged psychologists with psychologism—attempt-
work in psychology conducted within Bühler’s framework. ing to answer a philosophical question by empirical
To begin with he conducted investigations in both, thinking (psychological) means. In contrast, psychologists (such as
psychology and methodology. Popper achieved a major Piaget) charged philosophers with the fallacy of logicism—
breakthrough by radically separating logic from psycholo- attempting to answer empirical question by philosophical
gy. Popper’s philosophy of science, with its emphasis on means.
the method of trial and error, is largely found to be based on Kuhn’s work brought a major change to the status of
the psychology of Otto Selz. It has been well established psychology. Kuhn, who had formal training as a
that Otto Selz laid the foundations for the psychology of physicist, asserted that he attempts a “social psychology
problem solving and the psychology of scientific discov- of science”(Kuhn 1970, p.21). Kuhn’s formulations thus
ery.2 Popper gradually transformed Selz’s anti-inductive could open up a dialogue between epistemology and
theory of problem solving into a deductive psychology of psychology, making the latter not only the recipient of
knowledge. Popper (1962) asserted in his famous essay that epistemological postulates, but also a science able to
induction is a myth, it is not in fact a psychological or participate in the production of theories of science and
scientific reality. According to him science, in contrast to scientific activities. The recognition of the role of social
our normal cognitions, progresses because it alone actively psychological concepts in explaining science was facili-
looks for and accepts negative evidence and will reject tated by historians’ turn away from the internalist account
previously held beliefs. Popper eventually developed his of science. Philosophers in the analytic tradition viewed
theory by abandoning the psychology of discovery and incursions of psychology into epistemology as assaults on
psychology of thinking—by giving priority to the study of rationality.3 They discredited psychological account of
logic over the study of subjective thought processes. theory change and psychology was relegated to the task of
Popper held a view that psychology cannot explain the explaining only irrational. Sociologists were also antago-
growth of knowledge. For almost two decades he thus left nistic toward psychological and computational explana-
psychology aside but in the post-war years he brought back tions. Sociological approaches denied the need for
logic and psychology together. psychological, and particularly cognitive, explanations of
scientific discourse.

Popper’s Philosophy of Science


Psychology of Science: The Unsung Contributions
The origin of Popper’s philosophy of science lies in the
rejection of three fields: the Marxist theory of history, The contributions of several pioneering and eminent
psycho-analysis, and individual psychology. After a brief psychologists, who are famous for their mainstream
involvement with Marxism and Individual Psychology, research, to the sub-discipline of Psychology of Science
Popper found the theories of Marx, Freud and Adler remain largely unknown. A prime example is E.G.
deficient in comparison to Einstein’s work. As a result of Boring, who is best known among the psychologists as
this dissatisfaction, Popper moved from psychology of a great historian of psychology. Boring has written
thought and discovery after years of work, and finally
developed a characteristic deductive stance in epistemology
and philosophy of science. Popper rejected induction as a
3
Popper did not accept Kuhn’s proposal of turning to psychology and
sociology. He rejected all psychologistic and sociologistic tendencies,
and furthermore said that in comparison to physics, psychology and
sociology were riddled with fashions and uncontrolled dogmas. He
2
Selz had already led the way by describing scientific research as answered Kuhn’s question, “Logic of Discovery or Psychology of
problem solving. Probably, Popper’s shift from psychology to Research?” with the reply that while Logic of Discovery has little to
philosophy did not break the connection of his thought with that of learn from the Psychology of Research, the latter has much to learn
Selz. from the former.
Psychol Stud

numerous articles in the philosophy of science, the most outspoken opponents of a psychological approach in
psychology of scientific discovery, and the sociology of science studies.4
scientific production. Boring had interests in the psy- Is his shift to Philosophy responsible for his unpopularity
chology of the history of scientific discovery, the role of among psychologists? Popper’s work ‘The Logic of Scientific
great men in science, and the problems of originality in Discovery’ starts with the distinction between Psychology of
science and scientific creativity. Some of his papers on Knowledge and the logic of knowledge (p, 30). Popper
psychology of science, have been reprinted in the History, (1962), using psychological arguments and data asserted in
Psychology and Science (1963). Similarly, as much as his famous essay that science, in contrast to our normal
Piaget can be labeled a child psychologist or cognitive cognitions, progresses because it alone actively looks for and
developmental theorist, he can also be viewed as a accepts negative evidence and will reject previously held
philosopher of science. Another stellar example is Mas- beliefs. It has been argued that Popper this way characterizes
low. Maslow even published a book entitled The Psychol- science as a unique psychological phenomenon. Popper
ogy of Science (1966) but remains relatively unknown regarded his 1920s work on psychology (and pedagogy) as
among mainstream psychologist for this contribution. On immature, made few references to it until his ‘autogbiog-
the contrary, scholar like Karl Popper, basically a raphy’ published in 1974. However it has also been argued
psychologist by training, is famous for his works on that in the late 1940s, Popper began using his psychol-
philosophy of science. His emergence as one of the main ogy again to support his epistemological positions
opponents of psychology of science, probably gained (Hacohen 2000). According to a philosopher of science
additional unpopularity among psychologists. Many stan- (Hark 2003a, p 487) Popper’s epistemology is rooted in
dard history of psychology texts either do not mention him German psychology,notably the work of Otto Selz and is
or do it sketchingly (for example, Popper is referred only much more intertwined with psychology than is allowed
three-four times in Marx and Hillix book Systems and by his own anti-psychologism. He argues that Popper’s
Theories of Psychology). In contrast one can come across Selzian stance in psychology finally enabled him to
recent reconstructions of (young) Popper’s roots in Selz’s develop his characteristic deductive stance in epistemolo-
psychology of thinking by philosophers and historians (ter gy and philosophy of science.
Hark 1993; 2000; 2003a, b, 2004). But ter Hark’s (2004) Thomas Kuhn, the historian of science, with a formal
impressive and important work has shown us how rich the training in physics, not only relied, to a great extent, on
intellectual tradition of Denkpsychologie (cognitive psy- psychology (both systematic use as well as informal) for the
chology) proved to be for Popper and philosophy, and it is development of his thesis, his work and interpretation of
desirable that psychologists go back to the same material scientific development, could make possible the recognition
to get a better self-understanding of some fundamental of psychology’s role in the production of a theory of
assumptions that have guided their disciplines during the scientific activity. In his famous book Structure of Scientific
last hundred years (Erneling 2010). Revolutions (SSR), Kuhn clearly acknowledged that he
Kuhn, one the most famous historians of science, in attempts a “social psychology of science”: … “it should be
contrast, endorsed psychology in a big way. Kuhn clear that the explanation must, in the final analysis, be
emphasised on the social psychology of research in psychological or sociological” (Kuhn 1970, p.21). Kuhn
contrast to Popper who believed in the logic of research. used research in Gestalt psychology to explain what
For Popper, the introduction of psychological concepts happens when a paradigm shift occurs. Kuhn’s writing
into explanation of scientific theory change was synon- give evidence of the following influences from psychology:
ymous with claiming that science is not rational. Popper
himself acknowledges a change in his interest from the
psychology of discovery to an objectivist epistemology—
that is, to the logic of discovery. According to Popper,
science advances by discarding false hypotheses and 4
Science Studies include philosophical, historical, sociological,
replacing them with ones that are better approximations psychological, educational or politico-economic study of science and
to the truth, a kind of asymptotic progression where technology. Science studies have been claimed to emerge as the
reasonable outcome of revolutions in the three major fields: physics,
science never arrives at a final, absolute truth but does psychology, and philosophy. Operationalism as a revolution against
come gradually closer and closer (Popper 1959; 1992). absolute and undefinable concepts in physics, behaviourism as a
This distinction between discovery and justification revolution against dualistic mentalism in psychology, and Logical
allowed Popper to bracket psychological processes and Positivism as a revolution against rational metaphysics in philosophy
were the three forces whose convergence into a common effort is
ignore them. Popper charged psychologists with psychol- effected by the Science of Science (Stevens, 1939, 251). These
ogism—attempting to answer a philosophical question by revolutions occurred almost independently, but a general community
empirical (psychological) means. He became one of the of spirit among them led directly to extensive cross-fertilization
Psychol Stud

a) the work of Piaget5,6; b) work concerning the psychology that the former was the domain of psychology, the latter the
of perception, especially the gestalt psychologists (Kuhn domain of philosophy, and urged a formal separation of the
often relies on gestalt switch; c) work in experimental two.
cognitive psychology, especially that of Bruner and However, the neat dichotomy has now apparently
postman (1949) and d) work in social psychology (see collapsed under the pressure of arguments showing that
page 240; Musgrave 1971). According to Kuhn much of the justification of scientific results cannot be separated
scientific behaviour derives from the psychology of from the social and psychological processes that produced
scientists rather the than logic of discovery. Kuhn’s those results. The contemporary scholars within epistemol-
interpretation of scientific development, in way, opened ogy and philosophy of science have come to take
up a dialogue between epistemology and psychology. In psychology more seriously. For example, Giere (1988),
Kuhn’s view, to fully understand the scientific revolutions, Goldman (1986), Harman (1986), and Thagard (1988,
we will have to understand the psychological processes of 1993) all use psychology to challenge traditional logic-
attitude change effective within the scientific community. based conceptions of rationality. But recent Popperian
This in turn could bring out psychology’s role in the thinking continues to dismiss psychology of science and
production of a theory of scientific activity. Kuhn also its integration in science studies. Some sociologists are
explained the crisis situation in science in psychological intensely antagonistic toward psychological and computa-
terms and particularly acknowledged the importance of tional explanations, even going so far as to propose a ten-
Piaget’s investigation (preface, vi). Kuhn, stated that he year moratorium on cognitive explanations of science
attempts a “social psychology of science”(Kuhn 1970, (Latour and Woolgar 1986, p. 280). In contrast (and quite
p.21). He argued that much of the scientific behaviour naturally!), contemporary psychologists are becoming
derives from the psychology of the scientist rather than the optimistic and opine that psychology of science can study
logic of discovery. Thus, Kuhn’s idea of developing a social not only the problems connected with the personality of the
psychology of science is potentially important for Psychol- creative scientists or creative workers in science; but also
ogy’s integration into science studies. the problems connected with the activities leading to
formation of science; and above all, the problems related
to science as a completed human product (See Gholson et
Conclusion al. 1989; Feist and Gorman 1998). This paper argues that
psychologists should explore the mutual influence—the
I would like to conclude this paper by arguing that role of psychology in the development of Popper’s
psychologists of science need to look into the works of Karl philosophy of science and Popper’s influence on the
Popper to trace the heritage of their nascent sub-discipline psychology of science. Probably it may also explain the
(which is said to have a long past but a short history). Popper integration and relative status of psychology in science
noted in his doctorate that it might be possible to construct a studies in general and philosophy of science in particular.
new philosophy of science by translating Selz’ s psychological Why Psychology itself has not been important sub-
theory into a theory of science. Psychologists should explore discipline in science studies remains an interesting question
the mutual influence—the role of psychology in the develop- and need to be discussed in the light of philosophical
ment of Popper’s philosophy of science and Popper’s perspectives. Recent philosophers like Steve Fuller and Ron
influence on the psychology of science. Philosophers in the Giere, for example, put psychology at the centre of science
analytic tradition viewed incursions of psychology into studies (though in very different ways!). The former linked
epistemology as assaults on rationality. For decades, philos- more to Skinner’s behaviorism and the latter to cognitive
ophers of science considered psychological studies of the psychology (Fuller 1989; Giere 1988). The way to study
nature of scientific thinking to be outside the proper scope of scientists is to look at their interactions with each other and
philosophical analyses of science. Reinforced by a demarca- the inscriptions that they produce (Latour 2000).
tion rule that distinguished between the context of discovery Philosophy answers the questions related to science in
and the context of justification, philosophers of science argued epistemological terms. History of science deals with the
scientific progress. Sociologist of science explains science
5
A footnote encountered by chance led me to the experiments by
in terms of social norms. Psychologist can make distinct
which Jean Piaget has illuminated both the various worlds of the contributions to the study of science through their tendency
growing child and the process of transition from one to the next.—T.S. to focus on individual level behaviours and interactions in
Kuhn, Preface, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (1962) contrast as well as in support to sociologists’ institutional
6
A footnote encountered by chance led me to the experiments by
which Jean Piaget has illuminated both the various worlds of the
and culture level variables. Psychology moreover can also
growing child and the process of transition from one to the next.—T.S. handle issues, which may be different from those of history,
Kuhn, Preface, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (1962). philosophy and sociology of science. The question of the
Psychol Stud

integration of psychological accounts of science is thus live Hacohen, M. H. (2000). Karl Popper-The formative years. Politics
and philosophy in interwar Vienna 1902–1945. UK: Cambridge
and important. Historians, philosophers, psychologists, and
University Press.
sociologists study Science in very different ways, focus on Harman, G. (1986). Change in view: Principles of reasoning
apparently disparate aspects of science (in relative autono- Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press.
my from other fields) and apply markedly different Jacobs, S. (1989). Karl Popper and Albert Ellis: their ideas on
psychology and rationality compared. Journal of Rational-
methods. Science studies can thus be both exemplified
Emotive & Cognitive-Behaviour Therapy, 7(3), 173–185.
and expanded through the dialogues between the disci- Kuhn, T. S. (1963). Essential tension: tradition and innovation in
plines. All inputs are necessary for an integrated under- scientific research. In C. W. Talyor and F. Barron (Eds.),
standing. Disciplinary detachment may result in myopic Scientific creativity (pp. 341–54). New York.
Kuhn, T. S. (1970). Logic of discovery or psychology of
vision. Psychology as an independent branch of science is research? In I. Lakatos & A. Musgrave (Eds.), Criticism
well suited to study the social processes of science the and the growth of Knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge Uni-
issues and assumptions related to science. Popper’s initial versity Press.
interest was psychology, not philosophy (Jacobs 1989). His Kurz, E. M. (1996). Marginalizing discovery: Karl Popper’s intellec-
tual roots in psychology; Or, how the study of discovery was
shift from psychology to philosophy occurred around 1928,
banned from sciences studies. Creativity Research Journal, 9(2 &
which was manifested in his doctoral dissertation, ‘On the 3), 173–187.
Problem of Method in the Psychology of Thinking’. Latour, B. (1987). Science in Action. Cambridge Mass. Harvard
Popper’s own writings have mostly ignored this phase. University Press.
Latour, B. (2000). When things strike back: a possible contribution of
Studies of Popper on psychology have only begun to
science studies to the social sciences. The British Journal of
appear in recent years. Moreover, historians and philoso- Sociology, 51(1), 107–123.
phers have their own version of Popper’s early develop- Latour, B., & Woolgar, S. (1986). Laboratory life: The construction of
ment (which is related to psychology). We, psychologists, scientific facts. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University
Press.
philosophers and historians of psychology should highlight Mahoney, M. J. (2004). Scientist as subject: The psychological
Popper’s psychological phase and can make use of the imperative (rev. ed.). Clinton Corners: Percheron.
claims that Popper’s philosophical breakthrough originates Maslow, A. H. (1966). The psychology of science: A reconnaissance.
from his sharply separating logic and psychology. Careful New York: Harper and Row.
Musgrave, A. (1971). Kuhn’s second thoughts. British Journal for the
examinations of Popper’s views are thus important for
Philosophy of Science, 22(3), 287–297.
Psychology of science, deserves thorough reconsideration Popper, K. (1959). The logic of scientific discovery. London:
as psychology can be taken as the trajectory of his Hutchinson.
subsequent philosophical thought. Popper, K. R. (1962). Conjectures and refutations. New York: Basic
Books.
Popper, K. (1992). Unended quest: An intellectual autobiography.
London: Routledge.
Stevens, S. S. (1939). Psychology and the Science of Science.
References
Psychological Bulletin 36(4), 221–263.
ter Hark, Michel. (1993). Problems and psychologism: Popper as the
Bruner, J. S., & Postman, L. (1949). On the perception of incongruity: Heir to Otto Selz. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science,
a paradigm. Journal of Personality, 18, 206–223. 24, 585–609.
Erneling, C. (2010). Between Selz and Popper. Philosophy of the ter Hark, Michel. (2000). Popper, Otto Selz and the Rise of
Social Sciences, 40(2), 311–318. Evolutionary Epistemology: Uncertainty, Vagueness and Psycho-
Feist, G. J., & Gorman, M. E. (1998). Psychology of science: review logical Indeterminacy. Synthese, 124, 193–220.
and integration of a nascent discipline. Review of General ter Hark, M. (2003a). Searching for the searchlight theory; from Karl
Psychology, 2, 3–47. Popper to Otto Selz. Journal of the History of Ideas, 64(3), 465–
Fuller, S., De Mey, M., Shinn, T., & Woolgar, S. (Eds.). (1989). The 487.
cognitive turn: Socilogical and psychological perspectives on ter Hark, M. (2003b). Popper, Otto Selz and the Rise of Evolutionary
science. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic. Epistemology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Gholson, B., Shadish, W. R., Neimeyer, R. A., & Houts, A. C. (Eds.). ter Hark, M. (2004). The Psychology of thinking, Animal Psychology,
(1989). Psychology of science: Contributions to metascience. and the Young Karl Popper. Journal of the History of the
New York: Cambridge University Press. Behavioral Sciences, 40(4), 375–393.
Giere, R. N. (1988). Explaining science: A cognitive approach. Thagard, P. (1988). Computational Philosophy of Science. Cambridge,
Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Massachusetts: MIT Press.
Goldman, A. (1986). Epistemology and cognition. Cambridge, Thagard, P. (1993). Societies of minds: science as distributed computing.
Massachusetts: Harvard University Press. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 24, 49–67.

You might also like