You are on page 1of 198

This page

intentionally left
blank
Copyright © 2007, New Age International (P) Ltd., Publishers
Published by New Age International (P) Ltd., Publishers

All rights reserved.


No part of this ebook may be reproduced in any form, by photostat, microfilm,
xerography, or any other means, or incorporated into any information retrieval
system, electronic or mechanical, without the written permission of the publisher.
All inquiries should be emailed to rights@newagepublishers.com

ISBN (13) : 978-81-224-2638-0

PUBLISHING FOR ONE WORLD


NEW AGE INTERNATIONAL (P) LIMITED, PUBLISHERS
4835/24, Ansari Road, Daryaganj, New Delhi - 110002
Visit us at www.newagepublishers.com
To
The Inquisitive Reader
This page
intentionally left
blank
PREFACE

Major technological innovations of the 20th century consisted of


• mechanical devices including the steam engine, the automobile, and mechanical
contraptions involving automation of the assembly lines of manufacturing pro-
cesses
• electronic devices and the advent of information technology
Advances in physics had a major role in many of these developments. This made some
observers suggest that the 20th century belonged to physics.
The other major driver of the 20th century economic development was the chemical
technology. Of particular significance were the chemical technologies related to crude oil
distillation, agricultural inputs, and pharmaceuticals. The major developments in the context
of the pharmaceutical sector consisted of the discovery of new chemical entities of therapeutic
value by combining chemicals whose properties are well established and protein synthesis
using chemical reactions.
However, there have been doubts about the sustainability of these technologies in the
future. The two major reasons are
• the fast depletion of crude oil resources has been eroding the input structure on
which many of these technologies depend, and
• significant, though perhaps unexpected, externalities in the form of air and water
pollution and the associated greenhouse gas effects like global warming
In addition, the use of chemicals, exemplified by the use of fertilizers and pesticides in the
era of the green revolution, had the effect of destroying plant nutrients in the soil and gave
rise to pest infestation largely more immune to the use of pesticides. These pesticides also
entered foodgrains, fruits and vegetables, and water that we consume regularly. Many of
these ill effects were recognized only belatedly.
There is a more fundamental level at which conventional technologies have been found
to be insufficient. It is obvious that every country wants to be self-sufficient with respect
to food and healthcare. The technologies that are currently in use have been developed to
ensure this. However, the green revolution in agriculture, which is vastly dependent on
186 Economics of Biotechnology (viii)

mechanization and chemical technologies, appears to have run its course and shows signs
of a decline in productivity. There is a possibility of shortages in the future if supply of
traditional varieties slows down and/or the demand outstrips present supply potential.
In other words, it has been recognized that most of the major technological inventions
related to these conventional technologies are already in place. New developments can only
be marginal. As a result, the technological developments in mature industries will be a result
of learning-by-doing and cumulative use of technologies. Therefore, the large corporations
will themselves undertake much of the R&D in-house. Limits on the potential of the technologies
as well as limitations of competence and organizational culture of the large firms restrain
further progress.
It was also pointed out that much of the technological development in the present day
technologies is a result of random search through various possibilities. There is no systematic
logical basis for progress in the R&D activities. This is especially true of traditional plant
breeding and the search for new chemical entities that have therapeutic value for the
pharmaceutical industry.
The usefulness of biochemical reactions, albeit at a rudimentary level, has been
acknowledged for many years. For instance, it is well known that bacteria are the essential
change agents to convert milk into yogurt. Similarly, yeast is used in brewing beer and wine.
Such discoveries were also a result of hit and miss processes somewhat akin to the discoveries
in chemical technology.
A major revolution, in the form of life sciences and biotechnology, emerged before the
turn of the 21st century. Modern biotechnology consists of a set of techniques that involve
manipulation or change of the genetic inheritance of living organisms including plants. This
technology utilizes some known biological processes to alter others found in nature. More
pertinently, modern biotechnology, operating at the more fundamental genetic level, renders
the process of change more specific to a given task and is more scientifically deterministic.
To be somewhat more specific, modern biotechnology is made possible by the recognition
that
• proteins are the workhorses of living cells
• genes are recipes for proteins
• specific genes are linked to specific cells
In other words, biochemical processes observed in living organisms can replace conventional
chemical synthesis to produce proteins and other chemicals of biological value.
The techniques of modern biotechnology can be broadly described as
• recombinant DNA (rDNA)
• monoclonal antibodies (MAbs)
• bioprocessing techniques (cell fusion, cloning)
Against this backdrop, the value chains, leading to commercialization, consist of the following
links.
(ix) Introduction 187

• Identifying and cloning the gene of interest (molecular biology)


• Bioprocessing (scaling up of laboratory technology)
• Clinical testing (of pharmaceutical products and field trials of crops)
• Production and marketing of final products
It was suggested that biotechnology
• has the prospect of reversing the ill effects of the earlier technology (usually des-
ignated as bioremediation),
• will probably ensure a greater sustainability of new patterns of economic development
However, progress in biotechnology has been somewhat slow probably because the limits of
traditional technologies have not reached menacing proportions as yet.
Of late, biotechnology and associated aspects of commercialization are approaching a
relatively stable pattern though further developments and changes are expected. A study of
the economics of biotechnology therefore appears feasible at this juncture.
The most distinctive characteristic of modern biotechnology is its knowledge intensity
both in the development of the basic science and bioprocess engineering. This has two
dimensions. Firstly, the R&D, that is necessary to develop scientific knowledge, cannot be
taken up by the large firms. For, they do not have the organizational culture and structures
to undertake basic research. Perforce, the R&D developments originate in universities and
research laboratories. Secondly, consider the process of such knowledge transfer to private
firms. In the context of conventional mechanical and chemical technologies the following
paradigm appears to operate. The university scientists that develop technologies train their
students in their use. In turn, private firms employ these students. They assist in the transfer
of technology and its implementation. Over the years, there is an adequate pool of expertise
(both in learning new knowledge as well as developing tools to implement them) within the
private firm. Hence, it would appear that transfer of formal knowledge is adequate only in
a mature state. Since biotechnology is in its early stages private firms do not have knowledge
workers and they also do not have any experience in constructing and implementing
bioprocessing tools (fermentation processes may be somewhat of an exception).
Hence, the scientists, who developed the technical knowledge, must work with the
companies that undertake higher levels of processing so that informal knowledge (intricacies
in its actual use) can also be transferred for its efficient adaptation. Such necessity for intricate
relationships persists even at the level of clinical tests (of medicines) and field trials (of crops).
These features make it necessary to visualize and implement novel organizational forms.
They include
• networking of major manufacturers with small biotechnology firms (that predomi-
nantly deal with knowledge intensive phases of the value chain)
• strategic alliances with multinational corporations
• full vertical integration (through mergers and acquisitions) and so on. On a few
occasions, like the Human Genome Project, even open source organizational struc-
tures have been considered efficient. Economic analysis concerns itself with the
188 Economics of Biotechnology (x)

relative efficiency of one of these arrangements over the others in terms of costs
and the private (as well as social) benefits.
Consider the network technologies, viz., transportation, telecommunications, and
information technology. Some of these are considered as public goods. To appreciate this, a
good road network is necessary to have an efficient transportation system. Similarly, a telephone
network is efficient only when a large number of connections can be handled. The internet
also has similar features. Consequently, during some phases of the development of such
technologies it was felt that the large and lumpy investments cannot be recovered by private
firms in a reasonable time and/or the products (like the internet) were expected to have
largely defense or public use. Public investment flagged off such industries and eventually,
once the base is set, private investments became viable. No such defense needs or public good
properties seem to apply in the context of biotechnology. Much of the R&D and investment
have been in the private sector though on occasions public expenditure has been discernible.
Large investment requirements are one feature of biotechnology. Further, since the
developments are in their early phases, there are pronounced risks of failure. These features
add to the necessity for organizational networking to share specialized knowledge and the
associated financial risks.
These organizational arrangements determine the patterns of R&D and investment
financing in biotechnology. One of the primary concerns of economic analysis relates to the
degree of monopoly generated in the process and the associated implications for biodiversity
(especially in the context of agricultural biotechnology and animal population).
Other significant features of R&D in biotechnology have been pointed out. First, scientific
discoveries are slow and consist of discoveries of the structure of a few cell lines, fragments
of protein structures and so on. Development of a final product (of value to consumers)
therefore takes time and may depend on the expertise of several scientists. Second, imitation
is simple, once the scientific knowledge is available, though the initial discoveries are not.
These features made it necessary to protect property rights of scientific knowledge. Secrecy,
as a mechanism to protect such knowledge, inhibits swift and efficient progress of technology
since no one individual or laboratory can have all the requisite competence. Patents and IPRs,
at the level of novelty of the discovery of scientific knowledge (as opposed to a demonstration
of the utility to a consumer), was thought of as an efficient way of protecting property rights
while ensuring a faster diffusion of useful knowledge. These features of biotechnology
exclusively motivated the change in the patent regime. It was also felt that patenting knowledge
(not merely products of use to consumers) is feasible because biotechnology developments
are not cumulative. In particular, it was noted that the discovery of one protein does not
provide the firm any specific advantage in discovering another. Note, however, that once
patent rights are granted, the exclusivity clause meant that other firms and/or scientists can
obtain information only on a contractual basis. Monopoly elements in these transactions slow
the process of knowledge diffusion.
The ensuing market structure and contractual arrangements condition the pace of progress
in biotechnology. They also determine the sharing of risks and benefits among the stakeholders.
Clearly, the economics of biotechnology must come to grips with these issues.
(xi) Introduction 189

There is fragmentary evidence that biotechnology will be more productive and cost
efficient, less expensive to consumers, or very profitable for producers except when they
charge exorbitant prices. Developed countries push for patents and IPRs only to ensure that
their industries and firms are established before any real crisis emerges. Others resist it
because they do not want this dependence on any large scale.
As noted above, no new technology can be said to bestow benefits without creating any
diseconomies. There is a fear that the biotechnology revolution, which operates at the more
basic genetic level, may give rise to mutations that may have far more devastating effects on
human, animal, and plant welfare. Private benefits of conglomerates, especially of the short
run variety, may overshadow these consequences as biotechnology gathers momentum.
Similarly, trade across national boundaries becomes especially susceptible to abuse if the
labeling and testing procedures are inadequate, time consuming, and/or expensive. Economic
analysis is concerned with these tradeoffs as well. Devising suitable regulatory mechanisms
and examining their economic implications becomes mandatory. This is also an essential
aspect of the economics of biotechnology.
As in much of the industrial organization literature there are two perspectives from which
a study of biotechnology can be approached.
• The firm (micro perspective)
• The developmental (macro) perspective
This book adopts the first route. The second approach is reflected in some books available
on the market. The reader may wish to supplement that information as the need arises.
The present book endeavors to cover many of the aspects of biotechnology alluded to
above. It is at an elementary level so that even an undergraduate student, familiar with some
basic microeconomic theory, can appreciate the issues and their resolution. Some basic
fundamentals have been reviewed in appendices 2 and 3 to assist the reader.
The material covered in this book was presented in an undergraduate class. I benefited
from the interaction and comments. Similarly, some of my colleagues and friends read the
manuscript and offered useful advice. They were helpful in improving the readability of the
manuscript. I am thankful to all of them.
I would consider my effort worth while if the reader develops interest in this emerging
area of economics.

Kanpur

November - 2006 T.V.S. Ramamohan Rao


This page
intentionally left
blank
190 Economics of Biotechnology

CONTENTS

PREFACE (vii)

Chapter 1 1-16
INTRODUCTION
1.1 CHANGING TECHNOLOGY ...1
1.2 MODERN BIOTECHNOLOGY ...2
1.3 ORGANIZATIONAL ISSUES ...5
1.4 PATENTS AND IPRS ...6
1.5 MARKET STRUCTURE ...9
1.6 ETHICAL AND ENVIRONMENTAL CONCERNS ...12
1.7 GOVERNMENT POLICY ...13
1.8 LOOKING AHEAD ...15

Chapter 2 17-34
ORGANIZATIONAL STRUCTURE
2.1 THE SCOPE ...17
2.2 KNOWLEDGE INTENSITY ...18
2.3 BIOTECHNOLOGY KNOWLEDGE ...20
2.4 NETWORK ORGANIZATION ...22
2.5 NATURE OF CONTRACTS ...25
2.6 SHARING FIXED COSTS ...30
2.7 ECONOMIC CONSEQUENCES ...32
2.8 OTHER ASPECTS ...33

Chapter 3 35-58
IPRS AND PATENTS
3.1 WHY PROTECTION? ...35
3.2 PATENTS AS PROTECTION ...38
(xiv) Introduction 191

3.3 BIOTECHNOLOGY PATENTS ...41


3.4 IPR AGREEMENTS ...44
3.5 TRIPS AGREEMENT ...46
3.6 CONSEQUENCES OF PROTECTION ...50
3.7 ISSUES OF CONCERN ...53
3.8 MODIFICATIONS TO PATENT REGIME ...54

Chapter 4 59-78
INVESTMENT AND FINANCING
4.1 THE ISSUES ...59
4.2 ROLE OF PUBLIC INVESTMENT ...61
4.3 R&D IN SCIENTIFIC KNOWLEDGE ...64
4.4 RISKS OF R&D ...66
4.5 COMPLEMENTARY R&D ...69
4.6 AGRICULTURAL EXTENSION SERVICES ...70
4.7 BIOPROCESSING ...72
4.8 PHYSICAL CAPITAL ...73
4.9 FINANCING CONSTRAINTS ...76
4.10 FURTHER CONSIDERATIONS ...78

Chapter 5 79-96
DEMAND, COST, AND PRODUCTIVITY
5.1 THE BACKGROUND ...79
5.2 PATTERNS OF DEMAND ...81
5.3 PRODUCTIVITY ...85
5.4 VARIABLE COSTS ...89
5.5 WELFARE EFFECTS ...93
5.6 SUMMING UP ...96

Chapter 6 97-112
MARKET STRUCTURE AND PRICING
6.1 NATURE OF MARKETS ...97
6.2 DEFINING MARKET CONCENTRATION ...99
6.3 SOURCES OF CONCENTRATION ...101
6.4 MONOPOLY POWER AND PRICING ...102
6.5 DIFFERENTIAL PRICING ...106
6.6 DYNAMIC PRICING ...110
6.7 IN RETROSPECT ...110
192 Economics of Biotechnology (xv)

Chapter 7 113-124
ETHICS AND ENVIRONMENT
7.1 ISSUES AT STAKE ...113
7.2 ETHICAL ISSUES ...114
7.3 ENVIRONMENTAL ISSUES ...115
7.4 ETHICAL ISSUES IN AGRICULTURAL BIOTECHNOLOGY ...115
7.5 ETHICAL ISSUES IN DRUG DEVELOPMENT ...118
7.6 ENVIRONMENTAL ISSUES ...119
7.7 INTERNATIONAL CONVENTIONS ...121
7.8 LESSONS AND CONTROL ...124

Chapter 8 125-135
GOVERNMENT POLICY
8.1 AN OVERVIEW ...125
8.2 SCIENTIFIC R&D ...127
8.3 SCIENTIST VS. NBF CONTRACT ...132

Chapter 9 137-141
CONCLUSION
9.1 THE TECHNOLOGY ...137
9.2 ORGANIZATIONAL ASPECTS ...138
9.3 PRODUCT PROFILES AND MARKETS ...139
9.4 NEGATIVE EFFECTS ...140
9.5 STEADY STATE ...141

APPENDICES 143-164
APPENDIX I TECHNICAL TERMS 145
APPENDIX II ECONOMIC CONCEPTS 149
APPENDIX III MATHEMATICAL BACKGROUND 157
REFERENCES 165
INDEX 179
This page
intentionally left
blank
Chapter 1

INTRODUCTION

1.1 CHANGING TECHNOLOGY


Traditional agriculture was based on using nature’s bounties for crop production. In particular,
conventional farming
• uses seeds preserved from the previous crop
• depends on natural sources of water
• utilizes natural manures (fertilizers) like cow dung, and
• obtains assistance from earthworms and wooden ploughs to improve the quality of
land
The productivity of land, that such farm practices sustain, turned out to be inadequate for
the food security necessary for the growing population.
Chemical technology improved the yield of crops by providing
• fertilizers (nitrogenous, phosphatic, and sodium) to enhance the growth of plants
• pesticides to control worms and insects that destroy crops, and
• herbicides to remove the growth of weeds
Nitrogenous fertilizers are based on the naphtha feedstock obtained from the distillation of
crude oil. Many chemical products (like Vaseline and aromatic compounds) also have crude
oil distillation as their base. Some of them involve fairly complex chemical technologies. The
acknowledgement that oil reserves are depleting very fast created an awareness to explore
alternatives.
The usefulness of biochemical reactions, albeit at a rudimentary level, has long been
acknowledged. For instance, bacteria are the essential change agents that convert milk into
yogurt. Similarly, yeast is used in brewing beer and wine. Though the existence of such
2 Economics of Biotechnology

biochemical processes is well known (once they are established through a trial and error
approach) the reasons for their occurrence is not well established.
The emergence of modern biotechnology is changing these production processes
significantly. This has the potential to operate in such areas as
• genetically modified seeds
• biofertilizers
• biopesticides and herbicides
• specialty chemicals
Consider the context of producing fruits, vegetables, and flowers. Plant breeding conventionally
meant identifying robust plant varieties, cross breeding to obtain more and better productive
varieties and so on. These methods and their success depend on random trials. On the other
hand, modern biotechnology goes a step further by genetically modifying the plants. This
process is more scientific, systematic, and predictable. Hence, the fluctuations in productivity
associated with conventional plant breeding can be largely eliminated. (Of course, it is not
always easy to establish the superiority of modern biotechnology in terms of the growth in
average productivity per se.)
The animal world is also expected to undergo a major shift in reproductive biology. For,
cloning with the help of modern biotechnology has the prospect of creating more and better
varieties.
As of today the entire pharmaceutical sector (diagnostics and therapeutics) depends on
chemical technology. This has been a hit and miss process as in the case of agriculture. Modern
biotechnology, operating at the more fundamental genetic level, renders the diagnosis as well
as medication more scientifically deterministic.
Modern biotechnology also has the prospect of providing biofuels to replace the rapidly
dwindling fossil fuels as well as biochips for semi conductor applications. However, such
applications will take more time.
Technological advances, propelled by the steam engine, the automobile and so on as well
as several chemical technologies brought about environmental degradation and pollution in
their wake. Modern biotechnology (and the entire area known as bioremediation) is expected
to be of valuable help in solving many of these ecological problems.
Stated very broadly, modern biotechnology, though not a total replacement for conventional
technologies, is changing the basic structure of technology in many areas rapidly.

1.2 MODERN BIOTECHNOLOGY


Modern biotechnology consists of a set of techniques that involve manipulation or change
of the genetic inheritance of living organisms. This technology utilizes some known biological
processes to alter others found in nature. Such a transformation leads to a technology of
greater productivity compared to what the natural processes themselves can offer.
Introduction 3

The techniques of modern biotechnology can be broadly described as


• recombinant DNA (rDNA)
• monoclonal antibodies (MAbs)
• bioprocessing techniques (cell fusion, cloning)
All the pertinent technical terms have been described in some detail in Appendix 1.
Such a transformation is made possible by the recognition that
• proteins are the workhorses of living cells
• genes are recipes for proteins
• specific genes are linked to specific proteins
Consider the above mentioned techniques sequentially. The rDNA technology allows direct
manipulation of the genetic material of individual cells. It can be used in a wide range of
industrial sectors to develop micro-organisms that produce
• new products
• existing products more efficiently
• otherwise scarce products (which occur in small quantities in nature and are very
difficult to isolate in pure form)
• microorganisms that degrade toxic wastes
• new varieties of agriculturally-important plants and so on.
Cell fusion is the artificial joining of cells to form a new cell by combining the desirable
characteristics of two or more cells. This technique produces large quantities of monoclonal
antibodies (MAbs). They can be used in the purification of proteins and the diagnosis of
diseases.
As mentioned briefly earlier, a clone refers to a cell or collection of cells containing
identical genetic material. Clones are produced from a single parent cell. Cloning therefore
consists of using clones to produce plants or animals starting from such cells. Cloning may
reproduce what is already in existence or create novel plant varieties that would not be
possible using traditional breeding methods. Some of this activity may read like science fiction
and involves deep ethical considerations.
Biotechnology, described in the form of the above techniques, is not an end in itself.
Instead, it is an input in the value chains with various kinds of final (i.e., marketable) products.
The relevant industrial sectors are agriculture, specialty chemicals and food additives, animal
products, pharmaceuticals, environmental control products, and bioelectronics. These can be
stated in somewhat greater detail as follows.
Agriculture – hybrid seeds
biopesticides
biofertilizers
plant breeding
4 Economics of Biotechnology

Healthcare – medicines
vaccines
therapeutics and diagnostics
gene therapy
Industry – industrial enzymes
polymers
biofuels
fermentation products
Environment – effluent and waste water management
bioremediation
biosensors
creation of germplasms
Clearly, biotechnology is an input in the value chains of these final outputs.
At a more fundamental level, the value chain of any of these products consists of the
following links.
• Identifying and cloning the gene of interest (molecular biology)
• Creating the hybrid cells
• Legal filing for approval and protection
• Clinical tests (for drugs) and field trials (for crops)
• Marketing the final product
A somewhat related area of biotechnology is also receiving attention for its commercial
importance. Note that the total amount of information, available in the form of techniques
of biotechnology, is vast and growing. The human genome project, that ambitiously attempts
to map the entire genetic structure of humans, adds substantial information database. The
area of bioinformatics therefore attempts to utilize the now available information technology
to systematize information retrieval in this context.
Two aspects of biotechnology should be kept in perspective before proceeding further.
• Each of the techniques in the broad area of biotechnology is an essential building
block. A variety of products can be developed on the basis of the same techniques.
Hence, the economics underlying the development of these techniques is crucial.
• Most of the issues regarding the commercialization of biotechnology are similar to
those of other industrial processes. However, some issues are specific to biotech-
nology. For instance, the ethics of using biotechnology based testing for cancer or
other severe diseases. Similarly, patenting processes was deemed inadequate be-
cause market competition is at the product level. Product patents came into force
from January 2005 under the WTO (World Trade Organization) regime. Even the
idea of patenting fragments of knowledge (not related to a final product of value
to a consumer) has been accepted in the area of biotechnology.
Introduction 5

1.3 ORGANIZATIONAL ISSUES


A systematic approach to the development of the various links of the value chain is a
prerequisite for any commercial success. A large variety of organizational arrangements
emerged. Each of these alternatives attempts to balance organizational (core) competence and
economic viability.
At a very broad level the organizational designs are based on their final objective. The
two distinct patterns are
• technology base
• product base
A technology based organization uses a technique of the biotechnology sequence as an asset.
It endeavors to provide mainly services. A finer division of these activities consists of
• sequencing and mapping
• gene target identification
• gene target validation
• protein target validation
• identification and optimization of the bioprocess
• clinical testing of therapeutics and pharmaceuticals
The basic stages of scientific development and bioprocess engineering are knowledge
intensive. Hence, basic scientific research is undertaken in
• university departments
• government sponsored research laboratories
• some large chemical companies that have expertise in protein synthesis
Clearly, the problem at this stage is financing because this phase of work is far removed from
a marketable product.
Bioprocess engineering is also knowledge intensive. However, it requires more than the
laboratory tools. For, the scale of operations is different by an order of magnitude. Further,
in the context of biotechnology the knowledge interface requirement is still rather high. As
a result the following arrangements emerged.
• Start a small biotechnology firm close to a university community
• The university community accepts contract research for a large chemical firm
• In-house R&D of the large chemical firm
Usually the financing is by
• the entrepreneur of the small firm
• venture capital
• finances from the chemical firm, or
• the government
6 Economics of Biotechnology

The contracts generally stipulate payments for reaching well-defined guideposts along the
way to the eventual scaling up of scientific knowledge for commercial use. It is not surprising
if, after a certain amount of success is recorded, the small firm is taken over by the more
resilient chemical manufacturer. For, it reduces their exposure to risk though there may be
a danger that the technology leaks out before the firm derives the expected gains.
The alternative is the more integrated product based organization. In this organizational
form the activities are sequenced with the development and marketing of a specific product
in perspective. For instance, a pharmaceutical firm may target
• diagnostics (for cancer, AIDS and so on)
• gene therapy
• therapeutics in general
• vaccines
• blood products
In the context of agriculture the final products may be
• seeds, e.g., Bt cotton produced by inserting the insecticide Bt gene from the bac-
terium Bacillus thuringiense (thereby allowing the plant to produce a toxin that
destroys the gut of the invading insects) or the Roundup Ready soybeans (Roundup
is a chemical herbicide from Monsanto that may destroy the crops along with the
weeds when it is sprayed on the fields containing the crop).
• pesticides and herbicides to be used for spraying plants (outside the seed)
Clearly, the organizational structure requirements are more inclusive. In general, they
may consist of
• in house development in large chemical firms
• obtaining technology by licensing
• creating a subsidiary
• forming a joint venture
and so on. Investments in product based firms are more risky but they create more profits.
The technology provider creates the value of the product and will endeavor to control
the value and share it with other market participants based on their additional costs, risks
assumed, and bargaining position.
In sum, it must be acknowledged that the developments in biotechnology are contingent
on substantial changes in the organization of existing firms or the introduction of new firms
at various stages in the value chain. The choice of the organizational form depends on the
stages of production that the firm undertakes, the tasks that it chooses to perform, the
expected revenues and the specific contract clauses it chooses.

1.4. PATENTS AND IPRs


The classical description of property used to relate to land, buildings, and physical things.
Industrialization and ownership based on limited liability added a dimension to it. For, the
Introduction 7

ownership of stocks and shares of a firm had to be acknowledged as property. The information
age and knowledge intensity of recent technology made it necessary to treat even scientific
knowledge as property. This is the most crucial dimension of patents and IPRs in the context
of biotechnology.
Until about the late 1960s experimental biologists, unlike their counterparts in high energy
physics and other sciences, were reluctant to reveal their results freely outside their laboratories.
The basic reason for this was the fact that a great deal of this fundamental research could
not be associated with any product from which consumers derive value. Since the patent laws
at the time applied the utility doctrine, i.e., the usefulness of information to consumers of
goods and services, secrecy was the only protection they had for their proprietary knowledge.
Knowledge diffusion, that is very essential to develop further results and at an efficient pace,
was difficult due to the secrecy.
Consider the case of an individual or a firm engaged in R&D activities related to
biotechnology. Their inventions may be at three levels: the basic science, bioprocess engineering,
or products that can be marketed to consumers. Examples may be genetically modified cell
lines that produce monoclonal antibodies for diagnostics and therapy, or genetic databases
that combine sequence data with protein structure and possible function. Inventions at each
stage, that constitute intellectual property, involve high fixed costs. They can be recovered,
through commercial exploitation, only over a certain length of time. There is thus a necessity
to protect inventions over the required time horizon.
One alternative available to the individual firms is to maintain secrecy of their invention
until they can themselves exploit the market. At the most they may license the use of their
inventions to a selected few who can be trusted to maintain secrecy of the crucial biological
material or information. Where secrecy is used to protect intellectual property, access to
materials and information relies on the negotiation of private contracts between the parties.
It may then be possible to recover the market value of the invention.
This approach protects the original inventor from piracy or imitation by competitors.
However, this has two deleterious effects. First, it forecloses the possibility of others developing
competitive technologies to produce the same product. Second, once the invention is known,
it may be possible to develop related products that are also of commercial value and value
enhancing to society. In particular, the pace of the genomics revolution (and the mapping of
human genome sequences) and the diffusion of those research results (including the algorithms
to analyze them) depends on open access to genetic data. The original inventor may not work
on the development of derivative products if the costs are too high and/or there is a fear that
they will erode profits from the original discovery. This will happen even if there is an
expected increase in social welfare.
The alternative is to provide the inventor monopoly rights for its use and/or sale for a
limited time period. However, it is necessary to ensure that the veil of secrecy is lifted. Hence,
the basic condition for granting a patent is that the inventor must disclose the innovation in
a written description in such a way that any knowledgeable person can put it to practical use
(move forward to develop alternative bioprocesses and/or derivative products).
8 Economics of Biotechnology

There were objections to patenting biotechnology initially. The United States Patent and
Trademark Office (USPTO) argued against patenting of genes on the grounds that they are
• discoveries (identifying something that already exists) and not inventions
• products of nature and not new
• the basic core of humanity should not be owned by anyone as property
However, a 1980 U.S. Supreme Court judgment changed all that. The Diamond vs. Chakraborty
case was about the patentability of a genetically modified bacterium. The court held that such
genetic material is patentable because there is novelty. Subsequent gene or DNA patents have
claims that they cover nucleotide (DNA or RNA) sequences that encode genes or fragments
of genes. As a general rule, of course, patents cannot cover a substance in situ (inside and
resident) in the human body. But they can if they are isolated from their natural source.
The principal requirements for patentability are that the invention is new (is not already
documented), involves an innovative step (not otherwise obvious), and has industrial or other
useful capability. In biotechnology applications the common forms of claims involve
• an apparatus or a device
• a process or a product that can be manufactured
• a method of treatment or testing (diagnostic tool)
In general, the inventors may include in the patent claims a wide variety of related activities
that can be developed in the future on the basis of the basic invention. The scope of claims
(or, alternatively, the breadth of claims) will constitute a legal part of the patent.
Two issues have therefore become pertinent. First, bioprocessing of basic discoveries
towards a marketable product may take several forms. In the IPR act of 1970 the Indian
government sought to facilitate cheap technology acquisition and to enhance technological
self-reliance. Unlike the Paris Convention it restricted the range only to process patents and
not product patents (including imported products with patented technology). This enabled
the Indian pharmaceutical industry to use its reverse engineering competence to develop
generic drugs for the Indian market. Under these conditions a process patent loses its value
before the fixed costs are recovered. Hence, under the current WTO dispensation the patents
are for products irrespective of the basic science and bioprocessing concepts involved. In a
similar fashion the Union for Protection of Varieties (UPOV) 1991 amendment for crops and
plants
• disallows farmers the privilege of retaining or re-using seeds for self-cultivation
• requires a plant breeder to buy genetic dependency rights before he can market a
“cosmetically bred” variety.
The general justification is that the yield vigor of genetically modified crops decreases in
subsequent growing seasons. There are several concerns about the ill effects of possible
genetic mutations as well. Second, the broader the patent the more difficult it is for others
to develop derivative products. As a consequence, the incentive for the original inventor to
invest further may also be dampened. Hence, the patent regimes have shown a concern that
granting a broad patent too early may inhibit development of related products that assure
biodiversity. This concern is quite evident in the context of plant and animal kingdom.
Introduction 9

The 1970 Act provided patent protection of 7 years for food, chemicals, and pharmaceuticals.
It was 14 years for the other products. Under the Paris Convention it was 20 years for all.
However, the current WTO TRIPS agreements impose a uniform 20 years for all products.
There is a different kind of concern with patenting diagnostic kits for cancer and other
dreaded diseases. The point is that a doctor’s use of these on a patient may not be ethical
if the patient has a chance of longer survival if he/she does not know that he/she is suffering
from and/or susceptible to such diseases.
On the whole patents
• may inhibit technological progress and increase monopoly power, or
• accelerate progress and competition by sharing information
Judgments, about one or the other being dominant, are contested.

1.5 MARKET STRUCTURE


Developments in biotechnology, both in agricultural applications and pharmaceuticals,
proceed in four distinct stages. In the context of agricultural applications they can be described
as follows.
• DNA sequences from various organisms (plant and bacteria) are inserted into the
genome of chosen plant variety. The new gene constructs have economic value if
they have the desired characteristics (herbicide tolerance or insect resistance).
• The innovator, or a new biotechnology firm, field tests the variety following
government regulation requirements.
• The firm then seeks deregulation from the government. Once it is granted the firm
may cross this variety with others and pass on its genetics without the necessity
for further approvals.
• Industrial production and marketing of the transgenic variety is generally taken
over by the large chemical companies already in the market.
The pharmaceutical sector also develops through four similar phases.
• The university or research laboratory identifies new genes or proteins as useful in
diagnostics or therapeutics.
• A new biotechnology firm (NBF) sets up a process for producing the drug.
• A NBF or a large pharmaceutical company then processes it through the five
mandatory phases of regulatory approvals. They can be designated as follows.
1. Filing an initial application with the regulator.
2. Phase 1 trials about the safety of the drug in healthy subjects.
3. Phase 2 trials about the effectiveness of the drug in a small sample of patients
with the target disease.
4. Phase 3 trials about the efficacy of the drug in a large sample of patients.
5. A new drug application for regulatory review and approval.
10 Economics of Biotechnology

• A large pharmaceutical firm then produces and markets the drug.


The firms in both these lines, if they can be so designated, are of two broad types.
• Research intensive companies that specialize in discovery and development of new
biotechnologies.
• Firms that specialize in commercialization and marketing activities.
The markets therefore consist of the linkages between agencies which produce basic
science, bioprocess engineering, regulatory approval, and production and marketing. The
usual contracts between them are for the offer of inputs, sharing costs, and sharing revenues
received (royalties). The necessity to protect secrets of intellectual property makes these
alliances take the form of networks. Their relationship and the choice of contract terms
resemble a bilateral monopoly. On occasions the contracts also provide the large firms the
first option to license new discoveries by NBFs.
More specifically consider the pharmaceutical sector again. One view of the evolving
market structure is that small companies will specialize in discovery and the large firms
(which produce chemical based drugs and are already familiar with clinical testing procedures,
the regulatory processes, and have the physical assets and marketing expertise) will concentrate
on the production and marketing of final products to the consumers.
The contracts between the firms at these successive stages therefore depend on the
• ability to raise finances from the government and private sources
• share of costs accepted by the parties
• risks involved in the transactions, and
• prior experience of the parties in negotiating deals.
Consider the market interface between the pharmaceutical firms and the consumers. A
firm, in this context, is not merely the final producer of the new drug. Instead, it consists of
the network of firms (institutions) that develop the drug. In practical terms this means that
there is a high degree of concentration for a specific therapeutic category even if it is over
the limited time of the patent. This is a consequence of the large fixed costs and possible
economies of scale.
However, the drug market exhibits two other specific features.
• The drug discovery process is not cumulative. In particular, innovations in one
therapeutic category do not guarantee a higher probability of success in another.
Hence, no one firm can command excessive monopoly power.
• The market demand for firms is fragmented. That is, the market leadership in any
one drug does not assure the firm that they will gain in related product markets.
However, the growth of the firm will depend on the number of drugs that it
discovered and marketed (horizontal diversification). In general, though, no single
firm can hope to command a large market share in the pharmaceutical industry.
An exception may arise if a large pharmaceutical firm is marketing substitutable drugs
based on chemical technology and biotechnology. For, there is a high degree of substitutability
on the demand side and there are economies of scope on the supply side. The economies of
Introduction 11

scope are obviously a result of common fixed costs incurred in clearing regulatory requirements
and the marketing and distribution expenditures. (Some details of the concepts and sources
of economies of scale and scope have been outlined in Appendix 2.)
In certain therapeutic categories the new drug produced from biotechnology may directly
compete with the one based on chemical technology and produced by another firm. The
markets and the prices for the drug will then depend on consumer preferences.
New entrants into final product markets, when they are competing with a large
pharmaceutical firm, are likely to face competition because they lack marketing experience.
Return to the market for agricultural biotechnology. There are some obvious differences
in comparison to the pharmaceutical markets.
• Suppose a new gene discovery can be inserted into a number of crops. Examples
are the familiar Bt cotton and Bt corn or the Roundup Ready soybeans and cotton.
It so happens that there are many more varieties of Roundup Ready soybeans than
there are of cotton. The soybean market is more competitive. However, notice that
all varieties are not equally efficient in all soil climatic conditions. This limits their
competitiveness.
• New discoveries in agricultural biotechnology are cumulative. A variety of corn
that produces more oil is initially discovered. In subsequent iterations the crops are
made pesticide free. Therefore, there are greater barriers to entry and the degree
of competitiveness is lower.
• Seeds, that contain the genetic coding, are both complementary and substitutable
to conventional chemicals and herbicides. For example, Roundup Ready soybean
seeds are complementary products to the glyphosate in Roundup. They are, how-
ever, substitutable to the herbicides traditionally utilized to control weeds in soy-
bean crop. Strong demand complementarities suggest that a single firm producing
both these products will be more profitable. For, this firm can price its products
so that the use of complementary products (tying sales) can be encouraged.
• Seed companies have sufficient monopoly power. For example, Monsanto makes
the farmer dependent on its chemical herbicide Roundup if Roundup Ready seeds
are used in the cultivation of soybeans, cotton and so on. Hence, they are in a
position to charge a technology fees in addition to a price for the seed. In part this
may be necessitated by the high fixed cost of producing biotechnology embodied
seeds.
• There are fairly stringent standards to ensure food safety. For instance, in the U.S.A.
the tolerance level of Bt toxins is 5 percent. In the European Union it is even more
stringent at 1 percent. Even so, the consumer preferences are still toward non-GM
(genetically modified) foods in contrast to GM foods. This sensitivity has led the
firms to mandatory labeling of foodstuffs. The costs of transportation, storage, and
marketing of non-GM foods increased as a result. This aspect of the market inflates
the prices of non-GM foods.
12 Economics of Biotechnology

The economic analysis of the markets for biotechnology must reflect these features explicitly
in its modeling efforts.

1.6 ETHICAL AND ENVIRONMENTAL CONCERNS


From the time of the green revolution farmers have been utilizing large quantities of
fertilizers, other nutrients, pesticides, and so on. One of the major problems has been the
reduction of soil fertility and the ability of the soils to regenerate their productivity. Secondly,
a substantial portion of these chemicals are drained out into the surrounding fields. This too
has the potential to adversely affect farm productivity and reduce the capacity of the ecosystem
to return to normalcy following the initial disturbance. Thirdly, it was observed that crops
produced on such farmlands contain pesticide residues. In sum, ecological and health related
issues have been raised in the context of the use of conventional chemicals.
Genetic modification of crops raises a series of related issues. First, whenever plants
contain traits of herbicide tolerance and insect resistance there is a risk of such species
surviving the crop cycle and leading to the creation of more herbicide resistant weeds and
insects. That is, the planting of GM crops may induce genetic alterations of wild plants and
genetic pools of major insects. Second, when agricultural inputs flow into surrounding farm
lands the possibility of aggressive insect populations finding their way into those farm lands
increases. In addition, wind blown pollen from Bt crops may affect natural surroundings. In
particular, it was reported that such pollen has killed insects like the monarch butterfly. Third,
there has been a concern that Bt crops may damage biochemical cycles. Toxic wastes from
such GM plants may enter the soil through the roots. Similarly, such toxins may also reach
the soil when the plants are decomposed on the farm after the harvest. In turn, they may affect
a whole range of interacting species like bacteria, viruses, and insects.
At a different level, there have been concerns about the safety of GM foods with respect
to human and animal consumption. It has been suggested that the new proteins formed in
the food products based on biotechnology may
• themselves act as allergens or toxins
• alter the metabolism of the food producing plant causing it to produce new aller-
gens or toxins
Equally important is the concern that the genetically modified foods reduce their nutritional
value. For instance, it was pointed out that herbicide resistant soybeans contain smaller
amounts of isoflavons, which are important phytoestrogens, believed to prevent many
cancers in women.
Historically, farmers relied on the seeds produced on their farms for crop production in
subsequent years. This resulted in natural adaptation of seed varieties to local agro-climatic
conditions. Such rich biodiversity had an essential role in preserving the productivity of farm
lands. The widespread use of homogenous genetically modified varieties will unavoidably
lead to erosion of such biodiversity. The problem gets compounded by the fact that the earlier
non-GM varieties deteriorate over time if they are not cultivated over long stretches of time.
Introduction 13

The risks of biotechnology may then be summarized as follows.


• Invasive weeds and insect species may be created
• Wild pools of species may be contaminated
• Monoculture may lead to the neglect of traditional varieties
• There will be a reduction in biodiversity
• There will be negative effects on humans and animals when they consume GM
products.
In the final analysis the policy maker must examine the trade-off between the positive and
negative effects of both conventional chemical use and the new biotechnology adaptations.
The Cartagena protocol on biosafety 2003 is the main international agreement that provides
guidelines to national governments in issues pertaining to biodiversity. The approach is
precautionary. It attempts to prevent harm by banning uncertain products. Similarly, the
Indian Environmental Act 1986 attempted to ensure biosafety by stipulating that while planting
Bt varieties the farmers should maintain a buffer zone around their farm areas. In the final
analysis, disseminating information and labeling products may shift the choices to the consumer.
Two major concerns have been expressed with regard to the therapeutic applications of
biotechnology.
• There is a possibility of creating antibiotic resistant genes
• The new drugs may have potential allergic reactions
• While diagnostic kits for cancer, AIDS and so on may be an advantage to those that
voluntarily use them there are ethical issues about the physicians using them on
patients without their consent.
The pharmaceutical market is far more organized compared to the agricultural sector. Hence,
GM products of the pharmaceutical companies, when they are released on the market, may be more
reliable.

1.7 GOVERNMENT POLICY


There is widespread recognition that basic scientific research
• emerges only as a result of uncertain search however organized it may be, and
• takes a long time before anything of commercial value emerges.
Private firms do finance some scientific research. However, history is replete with examples
where the basic research funding is initially provided by the government. One of the more
recent examples is that of the internet. It was initially funded and developed for defense
purposes in the U.S.A. The search for new materials, especially those with potential for
replacement of fossil fuels or solving major health problems, have been receiving attention
from about 1970. Basic biotechnology research is of this genre. Successful research is then
transferred to the private sector for commercial exploitation.
14 Economics of Biotechnology

In general, governments refrained from directly undertaking or financing applied


research. But it was found that government intervention is essential especially when quick
developments and practical use are indicated. The classic example is that of penicillin.
Briefly recall the following well known facts. In 1928 Alexander Fleming identified that
penicillin mould had antibiotic properties. Oxford scientists then spent almost a decade
isolating the essential agent, producing it in laboratories in small quantities, and testing its
clinical efficiency. The arrival of World War II necessitated the manufacture of penicillin
on a large industrial scale. The engineers, at the U.S. department of agriculture, working
on fermentation technologies, utilized government finances to produce output of penicillin
in industrial scale fermentors. After the war private firms used this technology in the
production of a variety of antibiotics. In the context of chemical as well as biotechnologies
there is an acknowledgement that different process engineering methods can lead to the
same final product. In the absence of product patents a firm engaged in bioprocess engineering
may not be in a position to recover its sunk costs if rivals undercut it. This feature is the
basic reason for government financing of some applied research as well.
In the context of biotechnology it has also been recognized that there will be lengthy
approval processes even after an industrial scale bioprocess is identified. This feature contributes
to further risks of private funding of such research. In some cases government funding of
pharmaceutical products, until they are cleared through phase 3 clinical trials, has been
sought. Alternatively, it was argued that 20 year product patents should apply only after a
drug receives approval to market it.
There have been debates about the efficient sharing of investment between the government,
private venture capital, and the private sector. The alternative of tax concessions to the private
sector for such applied research has often been considered.
Some areas of pharmaceutical biotechnology are under strict government supervision
both because of their cost implications and ethical concerns. They include
• laboratory production of stem cells
• regeneration of human tissue
• possible generation of insulin producing cells in the pancreas of diabetics.
The transfer of a successful technology to the corporate sector has also been a matter of
government policy. The following issues are pertinent.
• To what extent should the scientists, who are originally responsible for the inven-
tions, or the institutions they represent be compensated?
• Will a technology licensing and royalty share contract be efficient?
• Will a profit tax imposed on a private firm be adequate for the government to
recover the initial investment they make toward technology development?
The government is also seized with issues of protecting intellectual property from piracy at
least until the innovating firm recovers its sunk costs. The pros and cons of providing such
monopoly power have been extensively investigated.
Introduction 15

Consider the context of agricultural biotechnology. The farming community is fragmented,


accustomed to certain practices (such as replanting seed saved from the farm), and find it
difficult to acquire the new knowledge and practice it efficiently. The need for extension
education is far more important now than it was earlier. The costs, to the private firms producing
GM seeds etc., is excessive. For, the fine tuning of agronomic processes is highly location
specific. Government organizations are perforce the change agents even in such a context.
The products of biotechnology, in the areas of agriculture as well as pharmaceuticals,
require a close scrutiny and on a recurrent basis simply because they have profound implications
for the safety of human health. Setting standards, testing and certification, and monitoring
performance have also become essential functions of the government. In general, providing
appropriate information coupled with monitoring has become an important function of the
government agencies.
Will these government policies be sufficient to ensure that
• the farmer and the consumer get fair prices
• the price of pharmaceuticals and the quantities supplied adhere to welfare maxi-
mizing norms?
We cannot be sure of these once a monopoly is granted to some firms. Once again it is
imperative that the government restructure antitrust policies, price controls (in the form of
differential pricing) and so on.
Drug delivery is often conditioned by national health service policies. For, the services
rendered through this channel are as significant as the health care through private hospitals.
In other words, government policy has a profound impact on the demand for health services
in general and diagnostic and therapeutic services in particular.
It was already noted that concerns of biodiversity and environmental impacts have
resurfaced at a different and perhaps more difficult level. This is so despite the fact that certain
discoveries of germplasms are helpful in solving some of the environmental problems.
Government policy is also directed towards such issues.
Both agricultural biotechnology and pharmaceutical developments are such that they
tend to displace conventional chemical technologies and other related methods. They displace
workforce and render them obsolete unless their skills can be upgraded. The private sector
firms will not pay attention to this rehabilitation requirement. Government intervention is
again called for.

1.8 LOOKING AHEAD


Recall that both agricultural and pharmaceutical sectors have been dependent on chemical
technologies for well over fifty years. The most prominent technological developments were
based on crude oil and its distilled components as the basis. The erosion of this basis and
the ill effects of the use of petroleum products have been the driving forces behind the recent
technological developments. In particular, the biotechnology revolution is one such response.
16 Economics of Biotechnology

The basic purpose of economic analysis of biotechnology is to examine the following


issues.
• What are the inputs necessary to make the technology develop?
• What are the investments and costs of developing the technology?
• What organizational arrangements will efficiently move the technology from the
laboratory to the market and the consumer?
• Will such arrangements necessarily involve government policy? What are the con-
sequences of patents, government financing of R&D and so on?
• What will be the effect of new technologies on prices of products and consumer
welfare? In particular, what are the economic consequences of biotechnology dis-
placing conventional technologies?
• What are the regulatory measures necessary to ensure safety in terms of human
health? What price and welfare effects will such regulatory practices have?
The fundamental analytical tools are those of micro-economic theory and industrial
organization. Networking is one of the basic principles that need attention. The possibility
that product patents of biotechnology will displace conventional technologies and thereby
endanger biodiversity is of real concern. The economic implications of this are fairly widespread
and need urgent attention.
The conflict between private and social benefit at almost all levels of the organization are
evident. For example, in its seed contracts, for Roundup Ready soybeans and cotton, Monsanto
stipulates that the farmers should not preserve seeds even for their own reuse. This is
important to maximize their profit from the sale of seeds. Is it possible to argue that this
maximizes social welfare? If not, can contract law and IPR regimes be so structured as to
eliminate the ill effects? The economics of biotechnology must address even such issues
explicitly.
Market Structure and Pricing 17

Chapter 2

ORGANIZATIONAL STRUCTURE

2.1 THE SCOPE


Every firm, irrespective of the industry in which it is operating, endeavors to
• monitor opportunities for its growth
• identify its existing competencies and develop new competencies to take advantage
of its opportunities
• implement its choices by developing an appropriate flow of information and materials
within the firm.
In such a milieu the external environment of the firm will consist of the
• technological knowledge
• market for new products, and
• sources of finance
It may contain signals with respect to
• opportunities and profit making avenues, or
• threats and problems that inhibit development
The internal environment, especially its organizational structure and the core competence
of the management, may have to undergo substantial changes if the firm wishes to realize
the expected benefits. In particular, the organization of the firm should have
• sensors to monitor and analyze the external environment
• develop suitable strategies in reaction to these changes
• capabilities to make the requisite adjustments, and
• resources to implement efficient adaptations
18 Economics of Biotechnology

In this context the organizational structure defines the


• scope of the organization (e.g., in terms of the extent of vertical integration)
• division of labor between the subunits, and
• flow of work within and across subunits
Individuals, associated with the firm and/or working in distinct divisions of it,
• offer their expertise
• learn from each other, and
• internalize existing values and/or redefine organizational goals
Such organizational learning, and the synergies derived from it, are essential ingredients for
the efficiency of the firm.
Traditionally, the organizational units within the firm
• maintained their decision making autonomy, and
• bargained with the general manager for a common pool of assets
This is the general nature of a M-Form organization.
In sum, the basic interest of the economic analysis of organizational structures is to
understand
• how certain economic forces govern the choice of organizational structure
• how organizational structures affect productivity and growth of firms
• how explicit contractual arrangements between the subunits of the firm emerge,
and
• the implications of organizational arrangements for market structure and consumer
welfare

2.2 KNOWLEDGE INTENSITY


One feature of traditional industries, viz., the mechanical and chemical based activities,
should be recorded. Most of the technological developments in these industries were a result
of learning-by-doing and cumulative use of technologies. Much of the R&D was, therefore,
a result of the efforts of the workers within the firm. It can therefore be said that the knowledge
necessary to develop products and new technologies was easily available in most firms. The
more recent industries, such as information technology and biotechnology, are knowledge
intensive.
• The knowledge available within the firm is inadequate to develop technologies
and/or products.
• Scientific and/or specialized knowledge must be obtained from outside sources
• Assimilation of knowledge requires constant interaction with experts.
To a large extent this is a result of the fact that these technological developments are relatively
new whereas the traditional technologies attained a steady state much earlier.
Organizational Structure 19

However, it must be noted that the discovery of new chemical entities for pharmaceutical
applications and other technological developments in traditional industries have been
proceeding on the basis of random trials and a hit and fail method of analysis. On the contrary,
developments in the emerging technologies appear to be far more logically organized and
calculated. To that extent their discoveries are knowledge intensive.
Similarly, to the extent that traditional technologies are in a steady state, the basic scientific
knowledge is well understood, documented, and transmitted to the workers and engineers
employed by firms. In this sense the workers in those industries already have the scientific
knowledge and practical experience in their use to facilitate their participation in the requisite
technological development. It can also be claimed that most of the innovations in these
traditional technologies have been minor and the scope for any major breakthroughs is small.
The new technologies did not reach such a state as yet. Hence, there is a shortage of trained
scientists that can be employed in the industry and entrusted with the development and
discovery of technology. The newness of these technologies also indicates that every new
development is a major innovation that cannot be built in house based on learning-by-doing
of the existing scientists and engineers. Dependence on outside scientific knowledge is a result
of this state of the technological developments. Knowledge intensity should be interpreted
in this specific sense.
Therefore, the emerging knowledge intensive technologies do not strictly confirm to the
organizational structure logic alluded to above. Instead, they require a different type of
organizational structure for their success. In the context of information technology the requisite
scientific knowledge is often generated within a firm and protected mostly by copyright.
However, it cannot be presumed that all requisite knowledge can be developed and provided
in house. It is necessary, at least on some occasions, to interface with other firms (especially
smaller firms that specialize in developing fragments of a larger product). There is a necessity
for product specific networking in either case.
Such networks may be created from knowledge and talents within the firm, obtained
through open source strategies (hacking and value enhancing contributions, not destructive
activities, to source code is an example), or through business process outsourcing.
To elucidate this further, consider the following. Assume that the firm receives a contract
to develop a new source code for a specific task (usually called a product). To complete the
task it may be necessary to pool together the core competencies of two or more individuals
(or divisions) within the firm. A team (or network) is formed for a short time to complete
the task. It will be dismantled once the product is delivered. A different network is assembled
as and when a new task is to be achieved. Note that the network may elicit help from
individuals in another firm (e.g., a software engineer from Tata Consultancy Services in India
may be drafted by Erickson of Sweden). The team will be under the control and management
of one firm until it delivers the product.
Outsourcing is possible when the job can be divided into independent modules so that
close collaboration is not needed. The team members remain with their respective organizations
and get the job done. (It may be acknowledged that individuals drafted into a team need not
20 Economics of Biotechnology

belong to any specific organization. They may be independent experts providing their services
on a contractual basis.) Outsourcing is possible even when there is some cumulativeness in
the development of the product. Of course, this involves greater coordination between the
constituents of the network.
Open sourcing is a peculiar network when no specific product is targeted (it evolves over
time without any premeditation) and there is no clear a priori knowledge of which set of
hackers will be in a position to add value.
Note that contracting knowledge from outside eliminates the costs of developing and
maintaining a large variety of talents in house. The disadvantages of this approach relate to
maintaining an information base and the costs and risks associated with short term contracts
(e.g., frictions and delays in learning to work as a team as well as explicit payment mechanisms).
The specific choice of network relations depends on these relative costs.
In general, when they depend on knowledge intensity, firms learn to identify appropriate
network members and they in turn learn to work in teams. This process results in organizational
learning, spillovers, and concomitant improvements in technology and productivity. Network
organizational structures cannot survive if this is not the case.

2.3 BIOTECHNOLOGY KNOWLEDGE


In the context of biotechnology, the development of a commercially viable product entails
• basic research
• bioprocess engineering and the scaling up of laboratory technology
• clinical testing (of medicines) and field trials (of crops) and getting government
and/or regulatory approvals, and
• production and marketing of the product
No single firm has all the necessary expertise. Each successive stage of product development
requires the expertise of the previous level. This must be obtained through networking as
a result of the knowledge intensity. However, such networks are almost entirely with agents
outside the firm. Some open sourcing policies have been recorded. See, for instance, Rai
(2002, 2005).
There are several levels at which transfer of knowledge through network structures can
be conceptualized.
• Note that, unlike in any other area of science and technology, biotechnology activi-
ties like the discovery of a few cell lines, partial information about protein struc-
tures, and so on can be patented. The cumulativeness of knowledge towards the
development of products of utility to the ultimate consumer necessitates network-
ing in the first instance.
• After the initial discovery there is a necessity to scale up laboratory technology for
industrial use. This phase of development is also generally knowledge intensive.
Organizational Structure 21

• Once a firm develops a Bt or RR variety it will explore the possibility of introducing


both the traits in a crop. Even such horizontal integration necessitates networking.
• If a Bt or RR variety of one crop is successfully developed, the firm may entertain
the idea of using the technology in some other crop. It was noted that this would
generally require new knowledge that may not be available with the firm. This
horizontal expansion of the firm also dictates networking.
However, it is obvious that a firm targeting biotechnology development in agriculture
does not have any advantage in developing pharmaceutical products. At a more micro level,
it was noted that the synthesis of one protein does not provide the individual, or the firm,
any specific advantage in discovering another. See, for example, Giescke (2000) and Malerba
and Orsenigo (2002). Networks have different constituents and tend to be event specific and
of a very short run nature.
In essence, different combinations of networks emerged in the context of different
technologies and product applications. The three major components of these networks are
• scientists contributing basic research
• new biotechnology firms (NBFs) involved in bioprocessing (this is the most distinct
aspect of the industry)
• large pharmaceutical and seed companies at the downstream stages
Note that the NBFs emerged as the essential link between the scientific community and
the large seed companies and chemical firms engaged in marketing the final products. The
knowledge interface between the scientists and the NBFs that scale up technology is significant.
Further, the relationships are event specific and somewhat of a short run nature. Network
organizations will perhaps be the only efficient organizational choice.
Clearly, information and scientific knowledge is one pivot on which biotechnology networks
hinge. The other aspects of biotechnology knowledge that need to be addressed are
• large capital investments at each stage
• significant uncertainties associated with these technology developments
So far the emphasis was on the fact that one level of knowledge specialists do not know
much about the knowledge required at the next level. It is equally true that the scientists
and managers of NBFs do not always have the expert knowledge in generating the finances
necessary for each level of activity. In a similar vein, it may be argued that financial
arrangements also have a significant role in the development and marketing of a product
of biotechnology.
The large seed company or the pharmaceutical firm may have the resources but may not
be convinced of the commercial viability of a new idea particularly in its early stages. A
network relationship between a scientifically oriented NBF and a specialist financial company
may complement each other. However, organizational learning in networks at this stage may
not be as strong as it would be at the technological stages.
22 Economics of Biotechnology

The sources of finance are generally from


• the government (i.e., public funding)
• the venture capitalist
• the capital market (including debt), and/or
• the internal sources available with large firms
It is necessary to visualize an organizational mechanism to obtain an efficient mix of
finances if the product’s potential to maximize social welfare is to be realized in practice. In
much of the literature dealing with financial economics and financial management the optimal
mix is defined only with respect to the cost of financing activity. But, as Jensen and Meckling
(1976) and Williamson (1988) emphasized, each of these sources of finance has idiosyncratic
implications with respect to governance and organizational control. The organizational
consequences should, therefore, be kept in perspective.
Hence, in the context of biotechnology the organizational arrangements consist of defining
an appropriate combination along both these dimensions. Different combinations of networks
of firms emerged in the context of different technologies and product applications. This is
one of the distinctive features of biotechnology. Powell et al. (1999) and Niosi (2003) argued
that the network arrangements extend to all aspects of the value chain generally. They also
pointed out that the strength of activity in each link, and not just their number, matters. This
will be examined in detail in chapter 4.

2.4 NETWORK ORGANIZATION


The concept of a network organization and the reasons for its emergence in practice can
be examined more explicitly.
Consider the scaling up of a bioprocess once the basic science is known. To begin with
note that neither the conventional university organization nor that of a corporate structure
are conducive to the required development if they act in isolation. In particular, university
research is often
•directed to discovery and professional publication
•rewarding the scientists in the form of promotions, status, honors, and research
funding
• supportive of free dissemination of information
By way of contrast, commercial research is
• supportive of only that research that has a commercial promise
• secretive until the full market value is realized
• owned by firms and the reward structure is limited
These organizational differences are such that a formal organizational alliance between them
is impractical. In particular,
Organizational Structure 23

• information, especially knowledge regarding the use of scientific knowledge, can-


not be purchased on the market for a price. Similarly, it may not be available with
any subunit of a formal organization for it to be transmitted through a hierarchy
• in a competitive environment, with rapidly changing technology, it is necessary to
utilize opportunities as they arise and over a short time horizon. There will be
significant sunk costs if the formal organization sets up a subunit to internalize
every such opportunity. It may not be possible to sustain the unit over a sufficiently
long time to enable the firm to recover such sunk costs
A far more important problem is generally highlighted. Much of the scientific knowledge
concerning biotechnology is such that the mere transfer of formal knowledge is inadequate.
Instead, there is a necessity for more direct involvement of the scientist in explaining the use
of scientific knowledge and making adaptations to it as the need arises. This is necessitated
by the fact that scientific knowledge and technology cannot be formally codified and
communicated in writing. Further, the corporate firm may not have the competence to absorb
and implement such tacit knowledge even if it is offered. The appropriate form of the
organization should be in a position to generate absorptive capacity in the sense of accumulated
knowledge, skills, and organizational routines necessary to identify and utilize externally
generated knowledge. These issues have been highlighted in Liebeskind et al. (1996) and
Argyres and Liebeskind (2002).
The organization of bioprocess technology therefore entails
• access to complementary knowledge from sources external to the firm
• learning to coordinate different knowledge skills, competencies, and assets, and
• aligning incentives to foster greater harmony
The network organization is a solution to the difficulties of coordinating activities of
different institutions where different but complementary activities are undertaken with the
commercial exploitation of scientific research in perspective. In a broad sense it can be defined
as the relationship between different groups of individuals to exchange knowledge, services,
and goods with the express understanding that there will be mutual support. These groups
generally come together to execute specific projects over a short time horizon. In essence,
therefore, a network organization involves exchange between the firm and other organizations
(like the university scientists) external to the firm. It is generally understood that they operate
in an implicit contract based on shared norms and values. However, somewhat more
realistically, desired efficient behavior may be elicited through value sharing royalty contracts,
monitoring performance, and commitment inducing share of fixed costs and investment
financing.
The following advantages of network structures are evident.
• They enable NBFs to access more, qualitatively superior, and reliable scientific
knowledge and assimilate it more efficiently
• Transactions in network organizations, since they are basically short term in nature,
provide flexibility to switch sources at short notice
24 Economics of Biotechnology

• The association of university scientists with a NBF signals the quality of the firm’s
research to both the capital and resource markets
• Usually R&D of the scientists is financed by public agencies. To that extent the sunk
costs to the NBF, of sourcing knowledge, is reduced
• A NBF, that has a large number of connections with scientists, can prevent com-
petitive firms from having access to certain types of critical expertise
• The more scientists are working on a crop, the more likely they are to find new
research methods, new genes, new germplasms, or new knowledge about the crop
that will reduce a NBF’s cost of developing a new variety
• In addition to providing access to knowledge for immediate projects, information
from the external linkages may evolve into important sources of new product ideas
• A large number of links means that the NBF learns to adapt to diverse management
styles of the scientists or the universities that they represent. In other words, over
time there is organizational learning, though not about technology, as network
connections increase
See, for example, Liebeskind et al. (1996) and Audretsch and Stephan (1996).
However, it is possible to argue that NBFs do not have any additional advantages by
having many links with university scientists (i.e., over and above what they gain from one
such contact).
• Scientists may prefer secrecy with respect to their more promising discoveries. They
may agree to license only the least promising compounds. Conversely, NBFs may
not take up even promising compounds if they are already handling a large number
of diverse activities
• There may be organizational dissonance as the number of links increases. For, the
organizational goals may clash rather than synchronize with the goals of the NBF
It is therefore obvious that there will be diminishing returns to network size and the most
efficient size of the network depends upon the
• development of a specific product
• extent to which the participation of the knowledge specialist is a requirement
• cost reductions that can be achieved at the downstream level due to an increase
in the size of the network
• the extent to which scientific, technological, or market risks can be reduced by
pooling complementary assets and competencies
It should be acknowledged that the NBF may make the scientists share in some of the
costs of bioprocessing stage. This may be one mechanism to obtain greater compliance and
commitment. This approach may enable the NBF to take up a larger number of activities and
also improve the efficiency of the organization.
To this point in the analysis only the number of links in the network have been considered
to be important for the performance of a firm. However, it should be clear that the qualitative
and quantitative nature of the links matters. Hence, in addition to the number of links several
authors suggest other measures.
Organizational Structure 25

• Number of field trials or clinical trials (input measure). See, for instance, Oehmke
and Wolf (2003) and Schimmelpfenig (2004)
• The number of approvals achieved (an output measure)
• R&D grants obtained
• Number of patents filed
• The nature (e.g., equity participation) and quantity of financing
• The nature and extent of risks absorbed
Three observations are in order. First, a network organization need not necessarily imply
links with organizations or individuals outside the firm. Modern technologies, especially
biotechnology and information technology, are such that a task can be efficiently concluded
only by drawing on the expertise of diverse groups of talent. Hence, it has been observed
that whenever a new task needs to be tackled the firm puts together a small team from within
the firm so that they can network efficiently and deliver the required product. Clearly,
utilizing some outside expertise is one of the options in network formation. The team gets
dissolved as soon as the task is completed. Second, a particular scientific idea may not
translate into a marketable product. Hence, the network organization fails if it is entered into
too early. On the other hand, too late an entry means the scientist has already invested a lot
of money, is in a loss, and has very low bargaining power. Timing becomes the essence of
success. The nature of the network organization, even for similar products, may turn out to
be quite different. Third, a network organization fails in its function, especially in the context
of private industry, if commercial secrets cannot be reined in within the firm. Such a danger
may be particularly significant while dealing with outside experts. The purely short term
contractual relations exacerbate problems of this nature.
Thus, network organizations are gaining importance and have their efficiency generating
properties. However, it should be understood that they are unsuitable in some contexts due
to adverse selection as well as moral hazard. This is one of the reasons for some firms
preferring full vertical integration by merger or takeover.

2.5 NATURE OF CONTRACTS


Recall that the networking between university scientists and the NBFs is meant to
• obtain and implement scientific knowledge
• reduce uncertainty in market valuation of the assets of the NBF
• provide a greater assurance of quality (on the basis of the reliance on patents of
the scientists etc.)
• reduce costs of producing a given output, and
• share costs to elicit commitment
Each organizational relation with an external link in a network is a specific event. It may
not be repeated over time. However, it is necessary to have some formal agreement (contract)
for sharing gains or payments for achieving specific tasks. For, otherwise disagreements
26 Economics of Biotechnology

may arise ex post if it is left open. Stated somewhat differently, it is necessary for the NBFs
to exhibit equitable behavior in each of these transactions because trust and reciprocity are
essential for the efficiency of network relationships. For, in the absence of such trust it may
be difficult to establish such links in the future even if they are desirable and necessary.
Stated more explicitly, a specific contract between a star scientist and a NBF will be to
• cooperate and create the synergy necessary for the success of the project on hand,
and
• share in the value generated through bioprocessing
In most cases, there is an agreement, before the start of the network collaboration
• on the distribution of intellectual property
• on the property rights of the resulting patents, and
• the terms of license to other parties
Assume that the scientist offers his expertise and effort in scaling up technology. In its
turn, the NBF provides its skills in bioprocessing and incurs the necessary capital and other
expenditure. The NBF may expect a market value of its activity to be
m = expected market value of the commercially usable new technological development
Note that there is no tangible marketable output at this stage of transformation. Hence,
this is an imputation by the financial markets and/or the larger chemical firms who eventually
utilize this to achieve marketable production. (Appendix 2 contains an outline of the CAPM
concepts used in this context. This is one efficient method for evaluating uncertain projects.)
The value is achieved through the cooperative effort of both the parties. However, the
expectations may not be fulfilled. First, there may be an adverse selection of the network
partners. Further, after the agreement is reached either of the parties may decide to free ride
on the effort of the other. This reduces the value of the outcome randomly. Second, the
pharmaceutical sector (in particular, production of human health care products, including
human diagnostic and therapeutical products, and associated treatment delivery systems) is
characterized by severe competition (from the established chemical firms). This uncertainty
is compounded by appropriation problems (since not all aspects of scientific knowledge can
be protected by patents), high degree of uncertainty of returns to R&D, and so on. Hence,
NBFs cannot determine in advance that any particular R&D activity will lead to a valuable
discovery. The realized market value may be (m + u) where
u = a random variable
with E(u) = expected value of u = 0
and V(u) = variance of u = σ2 (a constant)
Assume that the opportunity cost of the scientist’s effort can be represented by m2/2δ
where δ represents the following.
• The degree to which the scientist has to participate at the bioprocessing stage to
guide the NBF. A low value of δ indicates that more informal knowledge transfer
and involvement of the scientist is necessary.
Organizational Structure 27

• It may also indicate the skills of the scientist in his interface with the NBF. From
this perspective a larger δ indicates a greater skill and a possible cost reduction.
• Greater organizational learning, if it materializes, necessitates lower involvement
of the scientist in the operations of the NBF. That is, a large value of δ may also
signal greater organizational learning.
The above specification posits diminishing returns to the effort of the scientist.
Similarly, postulate that
km2 = investment of the NBF in the organization
Some technologies are more expensive than others. The magnitude of k reflects this degree
of difficulty.
The only way to compensate the scientist for his effort is to offer a fraction α of the realized
market value. Clearly, a larger value of acts as an incentive for efficient performance. The net
return to the scientist can be represented by
πs = α(m+u) – m2/2δ
Note that the scientist may be risk averse. That is, he will find it difficult to accept a large
value of σ2 given his opportunity cost. Hence, the net value of the contract to the scientist
will be
Vs = αm – m2/2δ – λα2σ2
where λ > 0 measures his degree of risk aversion. On the other hand, the gain to the NBF is
πn = (1–α) (m+u) – km2
By way of contrast, the NBF may be risk neutral. For, he may be operating in several
ventures and can therefore diversify the risk. (However, note that his risk aversion, if it exists,
will not affect the qualitative nature of the results that follow.) Hence, the net value for the
NBF can be written as
Vn = (1 – α)m – km2
The scientist can be expected to choose m targeted for a given α. Maximizing Vs results in
m = αδ
This is often designated as the incentive constraint of the scientist. Clearly, the scientist targets
a higher m depending on
• his level of skill, and
• the share of value he can recover
One characterization of the behavior of the NBF is to examine the choice of α that
maximizes the total net value given the incentive constraint of the scientist. For, in the ultimate
analysis, the purpose of creating the NBF is to generate the maximum benefit for all the
parties. Observe that the net value is
N = Vs + Vn
= m – m2/2δ – km2 – λα2σ2
28 Economics of Biotechnology

The value of α that maximizes N is


α = δ/(δ + 2kδ2 + 2λσ2)
The net value of this network organization turns out to be
N1 = δ2/2(δ + 2kδ2 + 2λσ2)
This is an increasing function of δ.
Observe that as δ → ∞ the scientist need not incur any cost in his association with the NBF.
That is, the knowledge transfer does not require the expertise of the scientist at any informal
level. Instead, knowledge transfer is purely formal. Under these conditions scientific knowledge
can be procured by making a fixed technology payment. There will be no necessity to offer
royalties proportional to the value generated. This is the implication of α → 0 as δ → ∞. Further,
organizational learning in the network relationship can be represented by an increase in δ and/
or a reduction in k. For, ultimately, one or both the parties become more efficient if they learn
about the knowledge requirements of the other through their association in the network. A
reduction in k, given the costs of the scientist, implies that the scientist is accepting a greater
share of the cost. Hence, he must receive a greater share α of the value generated. It can also
be verified that the total output obtained from the network relationship is
T = δ2/(δ + 2kδ2 + 2λσ2)
and the total cost of producing this output is
C = δ3(1 + 2kδ)/2(δ + 2kδ2 + 2λσ2)2
It can therefore be inferred that the productivity of the network organization is
P1 = 2 +4λσ2/δ(1 + 2kδ)
The advantages of networking will be lower, if the value of the informal interaction of the
scientist goes down. Similarly, an increase in organizational learning increases productivity.
The following model reflects some of the economic implications of an increase in the size
of the network organization. The profits of each firm can be represented by
πs = α(m + u) – m2/2δ
so that
m = αδ
as before. The NBF, or the large firm as the case may be, produces
m* = nαδ
if it has n links with upstream firms. Given the organizational dissonance alluded to earlier
the investment and spending by the larger firm will be kn2m2. Then, it follows that
πn = n(1–α) (m + u) – km2n2
and the net value of the network of alliances is
N = nαδ – nα2δ/2 – kn2α2δ2 – λnα2σ2
Organizational Structure 29

The optimal choice of α will therefore be


α = δ/(δ +2λσ2 + 2kνδ2)
and the total output is
T = nδ2/(δ +2λσ2 + 2knδ2)
The total cost of producing this output is
C = nδ3(1 + 2knδ)/2(δ + 2λσ2 + 2knδ2)2
Consequently, the productivity of the network becomes
P2 = 2 + 4λσ2/δ(1 + 2knδ)
This expression decreases as n increases. That is, productivity decreases as the network size
increases. Danzon et al. (2005, p.319) noted the occurrence of such decreases in productivity.
It can also be shown that the optimal n, that maximizes N, is given by
n = [δ(2 – α) – 2λσ2]/4kαδ2
Hence, n increases as δ rises initially but highly skilled downstream firms are unlikely
to find networking with larger firms profitable. Instead, as Danzon et al. (2005, p.321) pointed
out, “small firms take advantage of asymmetric information to out-license least promising
compounds (while) retaining their more promising compounds to be developed internally.”
It should also be noted that the large firms tend to prefer fewer network relations, each of
which yields higher sales.
The following observations are also pertinent.
• The fundamental basis for networking will be lost if the scientist need not interact
with the NBF in the process of transferring the informal knowledge associated with
scientific knowledge. This is reflected in n → 0 as δ → ∞. That is, under these
conditions formal transfer of knowledge and a payment of technology fees to each
of the scientists will be adequate and efficient.
• Though P2 is a decreasing function of n, it must be noted that T increases with n.
This is the only advantage of networking.
• It is of course possible that organizational synergies can be achieved at some stage
as n increases. The productivity of the network organization will be higher during
that phase.
• The maximum size of the network occurs when
δ = 4λσ2/(2 – α)
That is, the NBF accepts a lower informal interaction with the scientists the greater the royalty
share it must pay. Stated differently, a greater α will induce the NBF to choose projects where
they require only a lower continuous involvement of the scientists. Similarly, when the project
is less risky the NBF would be more willing to undertake it and it would be willing to involve
the scientist on a more continuous basis. It cannot, however, be claimed that the NBF will
undertake only those products that require this value of δ.
30 Economics of Biotechnology

Note that one of the advantages of the network organization is the expectation of greater
commitment. For, as Teece (1980, p. 232) pointed out, “internal trading changes the incentives
of the parties (i.e., aligns them more closely with the goals of the organization) and enables
… (them to attenuate) costly haggling … and other non-cooperative (disruptive) behavior.”
In particular, the association of a university scientist with a NBF will improve his competence
to move towards a marketable product. There will be a reduction in the scientist’s perception
of risk in the project. Further, the association of a star scientist may improve the image of
the NBF on the capital market thereby reducing the uncertainty in its valuation. It is therefore
possible that the variance of u becomes
V(u) = σ2/δ
The corresponding optimal value of α is
α = δ2/(δ2 + 2kδ3 + 2λσ2)
and the net value will be
N3 = δ3/(δ2 + 2kδ3 + 2λσ2)
Clearly, N3 > N1 if δ > 1. That is, the network organization is at an advantage whenever the
variance can be reduced through such collaboration.
The following observation is important in the context of agricultural biotechnology.
Usually the government agencies offer extension services to the farmer to help him improve
productivity. The model will be similar to the above. The farmer’s role is the same as that
of the scientist and that of the NBF identical to the extension service. Interpret m as the
gross welfare generated by the output produced by the farmer. The fraction of welfare not
accruing to the farmer goes to the rest of the community and not necessarily the agency
providing the extension services. The net value concept remains the same.

2.6 SHARING FIXED COSTS


It is by now clear that the question about sharing fixed costs at every stage of the
network organization becomes important. First, such sharing of risk may reduce the liability
of both the parties. Second, the NBF sharing in the fixed costs of clinical trials, drug
approvals, and so on will induce the NBF to offer the requisite intangible knowledge in
addition to the formal knowledge. It will then provide a commitment to the large
pharmaceutical company in so far as it transmits all the scientific information that it has
truthfully. Part of the reason is of course its own interest in recovering its investment. In
the process of sharing fixed costs the NBF also gains some control on the operations of the
large firm. As a result the NBF can scrutinize the decisions of the large firm and ensure
alignment with its viewpoint.
Let σ be the share of the NBF (denoted as F hereafter) in the cost km2. It will be assumed
that this has the effect of reducing the variance to σ2/s. More pertinent to the argument
will be the changes in the cost to the large pharmaceutical firm (identified by P in the
sequel). The following observations are relevant.
Organizational Structure 31

• P has to pay F an extra share of output by way of royalties due to the increase in
his share of capital and the increase in the bargaining power.
• P has to make greater effort, and perhaps incur greater costs, to convince F to
provide the commitment abinitio
• The costs of negotiation, management, and conflict resolution increase with s.
This may arise purely due to differences in expectations, management and orga-
nizational values. The costs of making collective decisions can be quite substan-
tial, especially when the firms have diverse preferences.
It will be postulated that αskm2 represents the total costs with the understanding that
αs > 1. The share of F will however be skm2. The profit for F will now be
πf = α(m+u) – m2/2δ – skm2
Given his risk aversion the value he attaches to πf is
Vf = αm – m2/2δ – λα2σ2/αs
Observe that F will not accept a large s because he incurs additional cost. Further, there is
a possibility that F experiences liquidity constraints while raising the resources required for
capital investments. Both these considerations suggest that F will prevail on the choice of s.
Hence, he can be expected to choose s and m to maximize Vf. This results in
s = (λ/k)1/2 (σ/δ)
m = αδ*
where
δ* = βδ
and
β = 1 – 2 (λk)1/2σ
The net value of the contract is
N = m – m2/2δ – αskm2 – λα2σ2
= αδβ – α2β2δ/2 – 2β(λk)1/2α2δσ
P will therefore choose
α = 1/[1+2(λk)1/2σ]
The efficient choice of s so obtained has the following properties.
• F will accept a higher s to counteract the effect of a low δ. That is, he will signal
greater commitment to P.
• There is a direct relationship between s and λσ2. A larger λ and/or σ2 necessitates
F indicating a greater commitment to P.
• As m increases P may seek greater security and commitment. F will therefore agree
to a larger s.
It must however be acknowledged that an increase in s beyond a point may be a
disadvantage to P because F gains control. However, the choice of an efficient s, whose effect
is through the variance, generally neutralizes the effect of a low δ.
32 Economics of Biotechnology

2.7 ECONOMIC CONSEQUENCES


It was generally noted that
• each NBF has associations with many scientists
• every large firms has links with many NBFs
• there are far fewer large firms in comparison to smaller firms
The economic reasons are as follows.
• Zucker and her associates argued that a large firm, which is already networked to
several smaller firms, has greater popularity as being reliable. This allows it to
increase its upstream connections.
• Under the existing IPR regime it is not possible for any one upstream firm to link
with many downstream firms. This is one reason for fewer downstream firms.
There are, however, deeper reasons for this phenomenon.
• Riccaboni and Pammolli (2002) argued that larger firms have certain types of
expertise like scaling up of plants, providing expertise in clinical trials and taking
a product through the regulatory process. However, these skills are difficult to
acquire. Hence, the growth in the number of downstream firms is not commensu-
rate with the growth of basic knowledge about biotechnology.
• Rothaermal and Deeds (2004) noted that by networking with a large number of
NBFs a large firm can prevent competitive firms from having access to certain types
of critical expertise. This reduces the number of downstream firms.
• Niosi (2003) noted that large firms have deep pockets (many sources of, and large
amount of, finances). They can use the finances to take up downstream activities
of a large number of NBFs. The converse is definitely not valid.
However, it is possible to argue that large firms do not have any additional advantages
by having many links with smaller firms (i.e., over and above what they gain from one such
contact).
• Schimmelpfennig et al. (2004) maintain that the more scientists are working on a
crop, the more likely they are to find new research methods, new genes, new
germplasms, or new knowledge about the crop that will reduce a private firm’s cost
of developing a new variety.
• Decarolis (1999) pointed out that in addition to providing access to knowledge for
immediate projects, information from these external linkages may evolve into im-
portant sources of new product ideas.
• Powell et al. (1999) argues that a large number of links means the large firms learn
to adapt to diverse management styles of the NBFs. This may help them develop
their network over time as also consolidate their advantage. In other words, over
time there is organizational learning, though not about technology, as network
connection increases.
Organizational Structure 33

• Rothaermal (2001) and Danzon et al. (2005) noted that large firms have cumulative
advantages of having been there already. For example, when they deal with a large
number of smaller firms, larger firms learn more about the differences in their
organizational culture, and develop greater capacity to adapt to diverse organiza-
tional arrangements. This organizational learning enables them to expand their
network even wider.
• Powell et al. (1999) also argued that as the large firms develop deeper networks
and also cover a large number of functions (scientific information, organizational
knowledge, and finances) they become central (or more important) relative to
competitors. This enables them to obtain larger research grants, non-operating
incomes, larger sales revenue and so on.
• Rothaermal (2001) and Rothaermal and Deeds (2004) also observed that incumbents
that adapt to the new technology via interfirm cooperation with new entrants can
eliminate competition while gaining advantage.
There have been concerns about negative effects and diminishing returns.
• Danzon et al. (2005) noted that there can be adverse selection. For example, the
NBFs may agree to license only their least promising compounds and develop
others in house. On the other hand, large firms may not take up even promising
compounds if they are already handling a large number of diverse activities or they
feel that the new compound will immediately cannibalize an existing drug that they
are manufacturing.
• Powell et al. (1999), and Decarolis and Deeds (1999), Bottazzi et al. (2001), and Danzon
et al. (2005) pointed out that as the number of links increases there may be organi-
zational dissonance rather than synergy because the organizational structures of
different NBFs may clash rather than synchronize with the goals of the large firm.

2.8 OTHER ASPECTS


The basic result of this chapter is that network organizations, i.e., contracts with one or
more outside agents, are essential when there is significant interdependence and internalizing
all activities is uneconomical. Such an organizational arrangement may improve productivity
if there are synergies and significant organizational learning. However, this cannot be taken
for granted due to the emergence of organizational dissonance as the size of the network
increases. In general, it may not be possible to turn an unsuccessful firm around by merely
adopting a network organizational structure.
In practice, there may be tendencies to choose n > nopt (to prevent competition from using
the assistance of the scientists) or n < nopt (if financial constraints are stringent). Some inefficiency
is bound to persist even dynamically. In general, it is difficult to assert that information
synergies dominate the network choice. As noted above, they may also be motivated by the
desire to monopolize, financial constraints, and so on. To that extent, productivity increases
from network organizations will not be a foregone conclusion.
34 Economics of Biotechnology

The NBF may invest a small part of the total requirement initially to ascertain the probability
of success. It may undertake the rest of the investment only with this probability. The
implications of such choices for the efficiency of network organizations have been examined
in Filson and Morales (2005).
When networking turns out to be inefficient some firms prefer full vertical integration
by resorting to mergers and takeovers.
In general, the existence of organizational learning and spillover effects in network
organizations cannot guarantee productivity increases. The exact conditions under which this
can be surmised with a fairly large probability remain an empirical question. Given the
present state of analysis any generalizations may be hazardous.
However, having a network is an advantage over not having it so long as it is utilized
judiciously.
Throughout this chapter diffusion of scientific information through a network organization
was among a limited number of clearly identified individuals and firms. This approach is one
way of keeping secrets among the members of the network. As noted earlier open source
policies may be superior if they can materialize. However, it is generally considered more
desirable to disseminate knowledge more widely. IPRs and patents provide a mechanism to
achieve this. The next chapter will deal with the pertinent details.
IPRS and Patents 35

Chapter 3

IPRS AND PATENTS

3.1 WHY PROTECTION?


A couple of decades ago, the legalities of obtaining samples of microbes from plants and
animals were straightforward. In many instances one could simply arrive at the site, collect
samples, and take them without bothering about legal issues. Such samples could be freely
transferred anywhere in the world. This is not possible in the commercial world of today.
Hence, it is necessary to examine
• the alternatives
• their evolution over time
• merits and disadvantages of each choice
At the other extreme, until about the late 1960s, experimental biologists, unlike their
counterparts in high energy physics and other sciences, were reluctant to reveal their results
freely outside their own laboratories. The basic reason for this was the fact that a great deal
of this fundamental research could not be associated with any product from which the
consumers derived value. Secrecy was the only protection for their proprietary knowledge
because the patent laws at that time applied the utility doctrine, i.e., usefulness of information
to consumers of goods and services as a precondition for the grant of a patent.
However, any one group of scientists has limited capabilities and resources to develop
knowledge efficiently. As a result, the developments in biotechnology were proceeding in a
fragmented way. Only a few cell structures have been discovered with difficulty. Further
progress, towards a protein structure or a marketable product was difficult and inefficient
due to secrecy. Secrecy, as an organizational mechanism, proved inadequate for efficient
knowledge diffusion. It was necessary to conceptualize an organizational mechanism that
allows fast and efficient knowledge transfer.
36 Economics of Biotechnology

Contract research was one possible alternative. That is, a scientist or a firm may provide
the knowledge that he developed, laboratory tools etc. to another scientist or firm who
maintains secrecy and develops them further. This organizational mechanism is subject to
three limitations.
• There is no guarantee that a transfer of formal knowledge is enough
• There is no assurance that secrecy will be maintained except in close knit groups
• Such small groups may not have the required competence
A better organizational structure was sought.
In the previous chapter it was noted that firms enter into network relations with suitable
parties to
• develop the scientific information that they discover
• limit the availability of crucial biological material to competitors, and
• internalize the informal knowledge that they develop in its utilization
Examples may be
• genetically modified cell lines that produce MAbs for diagnosis of diseases
• genome data bases that combine sequence data with protein structure.
Such networking is generally conducive to transfer of informal knowledge as well. However,
due to their short term and transient nature, such networks are vulnerable to knowledge
leaks. In other words, the synergies due to networking may offer an inadequate protection
in the pursuit of secrecy. It was also noted in the previous chapter that network organizations
may fail for a variety of reasons.
A further complicating aspect of knowledge generation and transfer has been pointed out
in Fink (2000), Bottazzi et al. (2001), and Grabowski (2002). As they pointed out, pharmaceutical
inventions are such that
• imitative product development (reverse engineering, generic drugs) is not very
difficult
• imitation costs are extremely low in comparison to inventor’s costs (scientific dis-
coveries in the pharmaceutical sector are expensive to discover, develop, and obtain
regulatory approvals)
• knowledge erosion is relatively fast since new ideas are generated all the time
The above features, regarding knowledge diffusion, therefore make these advances weakly
appropriable from the viewpoint of the innovating firm. That is, the firm will find it
difficult to recover the fixed costs of drug development if left entirely to competitive
market forces.
Since every stage of biotechnology development is expensive any mechanism that rewards
only the final product discovery (as with the market mode) does not compensate the early
discoverers who are essential to achieve the latter stage developments. This is the crucial
aspect of cost recovery in the context of biotechnology firms.
IPRS and Patents 37

Agricultural biotechnology is also subject to similar problems. In particular, Monsanto


and other firms invested substantial amounts to develop Bt and RR varieties of seeds. They
also invested in obtaining regulatory approvals and setting up marketing networks. However,
traditionally the farmers are accustomed to preserving seed for reuse. That is, the practices
of the farming community are inimical to the recovery of such costs. Hence, the plant
breeder, who made substantial investments in genetically modifying crops, cannot recover
his costs.
Note, however, that R&D can act as a barrier to entry. For, the speed of innovation raises
the costs and risks of innovation. This may result in a natural monopoly position. In such
a case there is no further necessity for protection. However, this appears to be an inadequate
mechanism in practice.
Hence, from the viewpoint of the innovator and the firm, there is a necessity to protect
intellectual property to
• provide security from piracy and imitation, and
• recover the large fixed costs of R&D
The necessity to protect intellectual property can be articulated from the vantage point
of social welfare as well. This too has the above two dimensions. First, it can be argued that
providing open access to genetic data is necessary to encourage the diffusion of research
results. For, removal of research findings (e.g., nucleotide sequences) from the public domain
will restrict development of derivative knowledge necessary to make the genetic information
practically usable. Consider the following example. Myriad initially developed BRAC1 and
BRAC2 breast cancer tests. By keeping the information exclusive and excluding other clinical
testing services from its use they prevented other firms from developing more and better tests.
Knowledge secrecy is therefore a disadvantage from the viewpoint of social welfare. Second,
under competitive market conditions, the firm may not be in a position to convert social
welfare into profits for itself. This would make it difficult for the firm to recover its fixed costs
while maintaining the maximum possible social welfare. This will be elaborated further in
the next section.
In sum, it must be noted that providing some protection may
• release knowledge to be used for common good, but
• creates monopoly power
thereby reducing the extent of social welfare achieved.
Mechanisms design must keep an appropriate balance between these two aspects in
perspective since it may not be possible to achieve both of them simultaneously.
Some changes were brought about in the early 1970s, viz., the introduction of
• plant breeder rights
• protection of plant varieties
• material transfer agreements
• copyrights and trademarks
38 Economics of Biotechnology

In addition, in some countries, it was made mandatory for all publicly funded scientific
research, including research tools, to be made freely available to all interested scientists and
industry within six months after publication. However, enforcing copyrights after publication
will be generally difficult for the simple reason that detection of violations is costly. A more
sophisticated institutional mechanism had to be conceptualized.
The only well known organizational mechanism was patents. There was some precedence
that pointed towards this alternative. First, in 1911 Learned Judge Hand upheld a patent on
purified human adrenaline made via a new process. The patent was not simply on the process,
but also on the purified natural substance. Second, in 1975 Kohler and Milstein, discovered
that individual immune system cells, that generate antibodies to a specific antigen, could be
fused with immortal cancer cells to create a small factory for producing antibodies. They did
not patent it. Hybritech was the first to use monoclonal antibodies in diagnostic kits sold to
doctors and hospitals to identify the presence of diseases (e.g., AIDS) or heightened hormonal
levels (e.g., pregnancy tests). It received a patent covering the whole family of diagnostic kits.
Patents generally provide a 20 year exclusive market protection if the following conditions
are satisfied.
• Novelty, i.e., it was not known earlier
• Non-obviousness; in particular, it is not something already occurring in nature and
not discovered earlier
• Full and complete disclosure so that any one knowledgeable about the trade can
reproduce the production process
In practice, patent claims should also specify their scope. That is, claims should define
what the inventor considers to be the technological territory that he claims to be under his
control by suing for infringement if necessary.

3.2 PATENTS AS PROTECTION


For all practical purposes it is obvious that there is a necessity to keep information and
access to genetic data open. For, this is the only mechanism to encourage diffusion of research
results and new innovation. It is also clear that there is a commercial need to protect inventions
in order to create revenues from investments in R&D. Patents are one answer to these
problems. Article 7 of the TRIPS agreement states the objective as “the protection and
enforcement of intellectual property rights (with the objective of contributing) to the promotion
of technological innovation and to transfer and (disseminate) technology, to the mutual
advantage of producers and users of knowledge and in a manner conducive to social and
economic welfare, and to balance the rights and obligations.” They consist of granting a 20
years exclusive market protection (i.e., monopoly use and marketing rights) in return for full
and complete disclosure of information so that anyone knowledgeable about the trade can
reproduce the production process. There is a possibility that some discoveries, e.g., a block
buster drug, may be in a position to recover its costs much sooner. Similarly, the costs of minor
IPRS and Patents 39

innovations may be low. This will also enable the firm to recover costs quickly. In such cases
it will be difficult to defend a uniform patent. However, this is the current consensus. Its
economic rationale is not properly documented. Such a patenting arrangement, by making
the knowledge available to everybody as soon as possible, is expected to enable others in the
industry to invent around the basic concept and create competing products. This process of
generating product variety under different patents for each of the variants is helpful in
breaking the monopoly granted to the patent holder.
Static micro-economic theory explains the role of patents in recovering costs in the following
manner. Consider Figure 1. In this figure D represents the demand for the patented product.
MR is its corresponding marginal revenue curve. MC represents the marginal cost of producing
Y units of output. It is well known that in a competitive market the firm will offer output
Yw on the market at a price pw. This maximizes social welfare and Yw is said to be efficient.
Innovative new products, e.g., crops based on genetically modified varieties, may have a low
demand at the outset. The producer surplus, represented by the area pwCE, may not be
sufficient to cover the fixed costs (not shown in the figure). This is the basic appropriability
problem. Now suppose that the firm is granted monopoly rights through a patent. It will now
choose a profit maximizing output Ym and price pm. This results in Ym < Yw; i.e., the monopoly
restricts output.
p,MC
G

Pm A

MC
Pw B CD
E F
MR
O
Ym Yw Y
Fig. 1
It charges a price pm > pw and the producer surplus changes to pmAFE. This increase in
profits (if any) may be adequate to recoup the fixed costs. This is the basic justification for the
grant of a patent. The emergence of monopoly reduces social welfare by the area ACF. This
is the conventional concept of deadweight loss. The agency granting patents should consider
ways of recovering the loss. Shavell and Ypersele (2001), for instance, argued that if the government
grants a subsidy pwCG the monopoly firm will indeed offer Yw. However, this is unrealistic.
Alternative solutions will be considered in the sequel. In general, it may be argued that the
patent system can, and does, make an attempt to put in place adequate instruments to curb
monopoly power of the patent holders in the exercise of the rights granted by law.
The other viewpoint, which argues that monopoly power can in fact be reduced, refers
to the possible cost reducing effects of the new innovation and knowledge disclosure. For,
this is one of the reasons why the new product is deemed superior. To simplify the exposition
40 Economics of Biotechnology

assume that the marginal cost


MC = c (a constant)
for all values of Y. Similarly, let the demand curve be
p = a–Y
Hence, the output Ym chosen by the monopoly is such that
c = pm(1 – 1/η)
where η is the elasticity of demand. Consequently,
pm = cη/(η–1)
On the other hand, the welfare maximizing Yw and pw are
Yw = a – c, and pw = c
However, note that
Ym = (a – c)/2, and pm = (a +c)/2
Hence, it follows that
(a – c)/2 = c/(η – 1)
Consequently, the deadweight loss is given by
D = (pm – pw) (Yw – Ym)/2
where
pm – pw = [cη/(η–1)] – c
= c/(η–1)
and, similarly, it can be verified that
Yw – Ym = (a – c)/2
= c/(η–1)
Hence, it follows that
D = c2/(η–1)2
Clearly, D reduces as c falls and increases whenever η is reduced. A very general result
is available in Rao (2004, p.329). This result suggests that the advantages of cost reduction
may reduce the losses due to monopoly power and the consequent reduction in η. Therefore,
it may be argued that monopoly markets, to the extent they give rise to dynamic efficiencies
emanating from the ability of large firms in the concerned industries to conduct socially
beneficial R&D, lower costs of production (process innovation) and offer a wide range of
product varieties (for instance, in a given therapeutic class and product innovation). These
will be conducive to enhancing social welfare.
An alternative approach to the welfare issue is due to Spence. Spence addressed the
question about the extent to which a firm can convert consumer welfare into revenue for itself.
IPRS and Patents 41

The standard Spence formula, explicitly derived in appendix 2, informs us that


Y
Yp(Y) = (1 – 1/η) ∫ p(y) dy
0
Hence, as η reduces a smaller portion of the consumer welfare can be converted into revenue
for the firm. That is, even if patents provide monopoly for the firm, it will prefer products
with a high elasticity of demand. If this is indeed the case the deadweight loss of strong IPR
protection will not be very much.
Both the approaches suggest that a high elasticity of demand will be less damaging.
Spence’s argument suggests that this will be the case more often. However, there is no
empirical evidence for this in practice.
Notice that the Spence approach is not designed to incorporate the effect of cost reduction
on social welfare. Deadweight loss calculations appear to be superior. Of course, it is quite
another thing to argue that policy considerations under the TRIPS agreement do not pay
attention to these calculations. Observers, like Watal and Mathai (1995), are only saying that
commercial interests of the larger corporate firms, rather than larger social interests, dominated
the TRIPS negotiations. The issue here is, should they? Or, is there a need for a balance?

3.3 BIOTECHNOLOGY PATENTS


There were objections to patenting biotechnology initially. The U.S. Patents and Trademarks
Office (USPTO) argued against patenting genes on the ground
• that they are discoveries (identifying something that already exists) and not inven-
tions,
• products of nature are not new,
• the basic core of humanity should not be owned by anyone as property
However, two 1980 decisions of the U.S. Supreme Court changed all that. The Diamond vs.
Chakraborty case was about patentability of a genetically modified bacterium. The court held that
such material is patentable because there is novelty. Subsequent gene or DNA patents have claims
that they cover nucleotide sequences that encode genes or fragments of genes. As a general rule,
of course, patents cannot cover a substance in situ (inside the body or resident) in the human body.
But they can if they are isolated from their natural source. Secondly, the U.S. Supreme Court ruled
that genetically altered life forms require patenting. A decision by the court allowing an oil
company to patent an oil eating microorganism (bioremediation) set precedence and opened up
massive possibilities, including that of the exploitation of genetic engineering for commercial
purposes. Lakhsmikumaran and Pillai (2005) pointed out that the Calcutta high court decision
in the Dimminaco A.G. vs. controller of patents and designs had a similar basis. The more recent
third amendment to the Indian Patents Act 1970, and its ramifications for biotechnology innovations,
has been examined in Abrol (2005) and Rangnekar (2006).
42 Economics of Biotechnology

In general, patentability and challenges to patent grants revolve around three aspects.
• To be patentable an invention must meet the requirements of novelty, non-obviousness,
and utility (note that utility is not the major emphasis any longer)
• The disclosure must be sufficient to enable everyone skilled in the art to make and
use all the documents of the invention claimed in the patents
• Claims should define what the inventor considers to be the scope of his invention,
the technological territory he thinks to be his to control by suing infringements
Biotechnology patents are peculiar in so far as they are not directed to any specific and
marketable product. Instead, biotechnology inventions cover genetic materials. The gene or
DNA patents generally relate to nucleotide (DNA or RNA) sequences that encode genes or
fragments thereof. They consist of a combination of definitions of new processes, methods,
and compositions. Genetic patents may also be directed to devices for use in testing and
diagnostic kits. In other words, some genomic discoveries have been granted patents based
solely on the new composition or sequences of a random piece of genetic material without
knowing its function but only in the hope that it will constitute an important part of a gene.
In general, patent applications may pertain to
• genes or partial DNA sequences such as cDNAs, promoters, and enhancers
• proteins encoded by these genes and their functions in organisms
• vectors used for the transfer of genes from one organism to another
• genetically modified cells, plants and micro-organisms
• processes used for the manufacture of a genetically modified product
• genetic tests for diseases that utilize genetic sequences or proteins
• drugs developed on the basis of the knowledge of proteins and their biological
activity
See, for example, Abrol (2005).
Stated mildly, there has been a greedy rush to apply for and grant patents though the
nature of the invention and its utility are at best nebulous. As Correa (2001) put it, “thousands
of patents are granted every year in the United States for minor, purely trivial developments
or for substances (including genes) that already exists in nature and which have been merely
discovered but not invented by their would be owner.” It is therefore necessary to recognize
that the most important task is to understand what a patent covers, i.e., the extent of protection
it provides the owner.
The scope (breadth) of biotechnology patents creates a host of new problems. First,
consider the possibility that a patented biotechnology material requires further improvement
and processing before any final product of commercial use emerges. The most obvious
example is the Cohen-Boyer patent on rDNA. If another firm wishes to pursue this activity
it needs a license from the patent holder. The patent holder may license the use of its patent
to others for an appropriate payment. However, a patent holder may hold rivals hostage
if they need licenses for a large number of nucleic acids. For instance, the development of
a medicine may depend on genomic technologies, receptors, assays, and high throughput
IPRS and Patents 43

technologies. Similarly, enriched vitamin A rice (popularly called the golden rice) is based
on technology that spans 70 patents held by 31 different organizations. This phenomenon
is usually designated as patent thickets. They tend to increase the transaction costs of
reaching agreements with various components needed to proceed with a product
development. Since each of these patent holders claims a royalty (a share of revenues
generated in the product market) the costs may increase prohibitively due to royalty stacking.
Second, some patents claim a very broad scope. For example, Human Genomic Sciences
(HGS) of the U.S. claimed a patent for a gene though its function was not known. It was
only asserted that it will be a research reagent or material for diagnostics. Subsequently,
it was discovered that it was the docking receptor CCR5 used by the HIV virus to infect
a cell. Thus, through access to a broadly defined patent HGS gained an undue advantage
to block further research. The patent offices have not been able to moderate such claims.
Diffusion of knowledge, the very purpose for which patents are granted, has been in
jeopardy. Third, the data exclusivity issue, though related to these, must be highlighted.
Many testing procedures for genetic discoveries and clinical tests of bio-pharmaceutical
products have been granted exclusive rights (often called data exclusivity). Usually the
larger chemical companies provide data relating to clinical tests on drugs and field trials
of GM seeds to the regulator while requesting marketing approval. Since these tests are also
expensive (accounting for as much as 50 percent of the costs of drug development) the
patent holder desires that the data be kept a secret unless they license their use to other
parties. The law allows this for a period of five years if the patent has not expired already.
This issue appears relevant for a country like India because it has the technical capabilities
to conduct such tests and the pharmaceutical majors expect MNCs to outsource such
business to them. See, for example, Maria and Ramani (2004).
In the context of agricultural biotechnology it should be kept in mind that plants and their
varieties cannot be patented through GM seeds alone. It is therefore recommended that plant
breeders and others be provided sui generis (literally second to none or a system of its own)
modes of protection. This will be considered in the next section.
In general, it can be claimed that companies may under invest or under develop
biotechnology products from the viewpoint of social welfare if IPR protection is defined too
narrowly. On the other hand, broadly defined protection may reduce competition and lead
to excessive monopoly power and high product prices.
It is therefore more reasonable to provide patent protection to functional genomic
discoveries that identify the role of specific genes and those that have implications for the
design of new products. However, it should be clear that the uncertainty about the scope of
patents can have considerable negative effects. For, firms may delay investments if they
expect another firm to enter the market under patent protection. But the patent holder himself
may also delay the exploitation of a patent if the extent of legal protection against imitators
is not clear.
Balancing the many aspects alluded to above has been a difficult task while defining
patent provisions and the law.
44 Economics of Biotechnology

3.4 IPR AGREEMENTS


It is generally argued that
• diagnostic, therapeutic, and surgical methods of treating humans and animals, and
• plants, animals, and essential biological processes for their production are not
patentable. This is the spirit of article 27(3) of the TRIPS agreement. In general, IPR
protections expect countries to put a sui generis system of protection of intellectual
property in place in all such contexts.
The IPR agreements relevant to the biotechnology area are
• plant breeder rights
• traditional knowledge and geographic indicators
• trademarks
• trade secrets
• bioinformatics and databases
Consider each of these in turn.
The traditional concern of the private sector plant breeding initiatives was on the
development of hybrid varieties. But, with the advent of biotechnology, new varieties displace
traditional varieties on a large scale. However, the habit of the farmer has been to reuse seed
from their crops for planting it in the next season. This makes it difficult for the breeders to
recover their investment. The Plant Variety Protection (PVP) certificates provide one form of
protection. Essentially, they protect the genetic makeup of a specific plant variety even if the
varieties have similar characteristics. The basic requirement is of novelty and distinctiveness.
However, there is a necessity for non-obviousness (inventive step) or usefulness (industrial
appropriability) as in the case of patents. The PVP system of protection also acknowledges
that products of biotechnology are essentially delivered through seeds. This may signal
preventing the reuse of seed if the genetic resources are conserved and maintained for
possible future use through “gene banks.” However, in practice, the more efficient mechanism
of delivery is “on farm” seed preservation. When this is acknowledged the PVPs make a
balance by allowing farmer’s rights consisting of
• reuse of seeds from crops
• use of protected varieties for further breeding
• cross licensing for development of plant varieties
However, in more recent times, biotechnology firms came up with “terminator seeds” that
are sterile and do not produce any crop if replanted.
There is also a recognition that the productivity of GM seeds depend crucially on the agro
climatic conditions that vary considerably. It is therefore possible to adapt a GM variety to
suit local conditions. See, for example, the evidence in Morse et al. (2005) on Bt cotton. It is
difficult to cover such a spectrum through a single PVP.
IPRS and Patents 45

Traditional knowledge about plants is specific to a region. However, its date of origin is
uncertain. So is its ownership if that concept is meaningful at all. In particular, the knowledge
is in unwritten form. It is, however, acknowledged that the variety of crops suitable to a
specific agroclimatic condition has evolved over time. Such traditional knowledge about plant
breeding is an important source of new varieties. It also provides the background stock for
new crops produced by genetic engineering. See, for example, Schaal (2004). Hence, it should
be protected. This is sought to be achieved through copyrights. The practical difficulty here
is in creating institutions and awareness about the need to obtain such copyrights.
Trademarks apply to all goods and services in a similar fashion. They also provide legal
protection for an unlimited amount of time. They are meant to distinguish goods or services
of one firm from those of another. Consequently, even colors and symbols constitute important
parts of a trademark.
Products of biotechnology undergo stringent tests, regarding human health and safety,
before regulatory approval to market them. The regulator usually demands such information
from the inventor. This information is also expensive and it was observed that it may account
for as much as 50 percent of the development of a drug. Hence, the inventors are interested
in the regulator maintaining secrecy (trade secrets) with respect to such data. This is granted
for upto five years after regulatory approval. During this period the right to license the use
of data on clinical tests and field trials rests with the original seed or pharmaceutical firm.
In general, it can be argued that the IPR system is driven by commercial considerations
of product differentiation and planned obsolescence rather than genuine improvements in
product characteristics.
Agricultural biotechnology is also posing issues of biodiversity and environmental concerns.
In this context, biodiversity refers to the variability among living organisms from all sources.
Such biodiversity, as observed in practice today, is a result of centuries of adaptation of plants
and other species to the environment they live in. Such biodiversity, as opposed to commercial
uniformity that biotechnology firms seek to impose through patents and IPRs, constitutes the
very essence of maintaining the ecological balance. Long term viability of biotechnology
necessitates addressing the tradeoff between commercial interests of a few and the ecological
balance necessary for the survival of many.
The Convention on Biodiversity (CBD) and Cartagena Protocol (2003) are the most pertinent.
The goals of CBD are the
• conservation of biodiversity
• sustainable use of its components
• fair and equitable sharing of benefits
• including appropriate access
• transfer of relevant technologies and products
To pursue these objectives, the CBD
• recognizes sovereignty of countries and their genetic resources
46 Economics of Biotechnology

• focuses on in situ (within the body) conservation of genetic resources (not in gene
banks)
• recommends protection of technical knowledge
The Cartagena Convention deals mostly with international trade. It emphasizes the need for
• an adequate level of protection in the field of safer transfer, handling, and the use
of genetic materials
• minimizing risks for human health, and
• monitoring transboundary movements
The following approaches have been suggested.
• Prior informed consent (based on scientific knowledge and tests); the exporting
country should inform the importing state of the nature and hazards of shipping
GM products and obtain written consent
• Refuse such consignments if not satisfied about safety or destroy the lot if illegally
shipped
However, one of the concerns is that such rejection will be a non-tariff barrier under the TRIPS
agreement. A resolution is not as yet in sight.

3.5 TRIPS AGREEMENT


Historically, each country specified its own regimes of IPR protection to suit their
development imperatives. The Swiss watch industry and German glass are examples. The
Indian pharmaceutical industry successfully developed the market for generic drugs as a
result of the Patents Act 1970 that allowed only process patents. A concept of a universal
patent does not exist. Firms must apply for independent patent protection in every country
where they intend to exploit their commercial interest.
Trading across international boundaries is assuming significance in recent years. The
Biotechnology Revolution and Information Technology are at the cutting edge of such
developments. This calls for some uniformity of laws in different countries to facilitate the
spread of knowledge and diffusion of innovative technologies. The TRIPS agreement under the
WTO is an attempt at such uniformity. The three broad components of the IPR regime are
• degree of protection; rigid and excessive protection
• use of patents and enforcement; abuse of IPRS
• dispute settlement; especially restrictions on technology diffusion
It is expected that TRIPS agreement will alter the patterns of
• technology transfer and imitation
• foreign direct investment
• domestic innovation
• international incentives for trade
IPRS and Patents 47

Assume that an individual or a firm in country 1 developed a new product and applied
for a patent in his country. The knowledge necessary to manufacture the product is no longer
a secret even across international boundaries. Hence, two possibilities exist.
• Another individual in country 2 may develop a somewhat different process of
producing that product, undertake manufacture, and sell it in his country.
• Having produced the output, perhaps at a lower cost, the firm in country 2 may
export the product to country 1 and undercut it.
The TRIPS agreement attempts to prevent these by insisting that
• patents must be for products and not just processes; what this means is that a
product, irrespective of the process of arriving at it, will be considered equivalent
and hence a violation of patent rights of the firm in country 1
• there must be uniformity over patent life over which the innovator will have a
monopoly right of refusal for others to use the production process; TRIPS defines
it as 20 years for all products and/or technologies
• the original patent holder should have exclusive marketing rights (EMRs)
The firm in country 1 applies for a patent in country 2 as well. Within the rules of the
TRIPS agreement country 2 can refuse the patent only if
• the products and technologies are morally or ethically indefensible
• they harm human health
• they are inimical to national safety
Three aspects of EMRs must be noted.
• Suppose the firm in country 1 applies for a patent in country 2. However, the grant
of a patent takes some time. Further, in the case of agrochemicals and products the
right to sell is commercially more critical. Under TRIPS agreement EMRs must be
granted to the patent applicant for five years or until the patent application is
decided. Of course, such EMRs apply only if the firm has a EMR in some other
country
• EMRs can prohibit imitators from selling the product in country 2 even if they can
produce it.
• The grant of an EMR in country 1 also means that even the patent holder cannot
import the product from country 2. This is a protection against the possible cost
and price differentials in the two countries.
It was necessary for TRIPS to address another aspect of patent grants. Assume that
country 2 granted patent rights to the firm in country 1. Clearly, they have done so, expecting
• the possible spread of knowledge and technology in country 2
• the availability of the innovative products in country 2
On occasions the firm from country 1 may try to use its monopoly power and refuse to
invest in country 2, produce the output in country 2, and/or market it there. This may be
48 Economics of Biotechnology

deemed an abuse of the patent. TRIPS provides a mechanism by which country 2 can force
the firm to issue a compulsory license to another firm in country 2. More specifically, a firm
in country 2 can apply for a compulsory license provided
• the original innovator does not start production in country 2 even after three years
of the grant of the patent in that country
• production is not started even after four years of the patent filing in country 2
However, TRIPS stipulates that the compulsory license need not be granted if the patent
holder can offer valid reasons. Suppose a compulsory license is not granted. Does this mean
that the patent holder forfeits his rights? TRIPS agreement allows the patent holder two years
time to rectify the situation. The rights will be deemed to have been forfeited after that.
There is another dimension of compulsory licensing under the TRIPS agreement. Host
countries may require the patent holder to provide a license to a local producer at a reasonable
cost in case of a national emergency. It is difficult to define what constitutes a “national
emergency” and what a “reasonable cost” will be. This may lead to violation of patents
somewhat arbitrarily.
Under PVP a provision for compulsory licensing is dictated by the strong commitment
for public interest. Under this provision a holder of plant breeder’s rights cannot
• refuse any applicant
• impose unreasonable terms of license
The material transfer agreements for genetic materials are also of this nature. Note that
this is important simply because most of the genetic inventions are not final products. Instead,
they have to be developed further. Hence, the spirit of the patent will be violated if knowledge
diffusion is blocked.
The TRIPS agreement considered one other aspect. Suppose the firm in country 1, i.e., the
patent holder, sold some units of the commodity to an individual X in country 2. X may, in
his turn, sell it to others in country 2. Will this be a violation of patent rights? The TRIPS
agreement gives the rights of decision to country 2. For, the patent holder is deemed to have
exhausted his rights after the sale to X. Assume that X sells the product to someone in country
1. Will this be a violation? As per TRIPS agreement it will not be so provided country 1 offered
a most favored nation treatment to country 2.
In the context of biotechnology the firm has to go through a regulatory approval process
after applying for a patent. In the context of agricultural biotechnology this involves extensive
field trials. The pharmaceutical sector has to go through clinical tests. In both these contexts
the patent holder must submit all the test data to the regulator. It was therefore pertinent
to find out if this data, like the patent filing details, become public property that everyone
can access freely. The developed countries insist that this expensive data must be protected.
Under the TRIPS agreement such test data remains an exclusive property of the patent
holder for five years from the point of regulatory approval or the end of the patent life
IPRS and Patents 49

whichever is earlier. Anyone else that desires to use such data must get a license from the
patent holder.
In general, the attitude of the developed countries is that they should have monopoly
rights
• over the technology since they developed it
• over production and monopoly pricing for goods that they alone can sell
• to make it difficult, if not impossible, for others to develop the technology
The developing countries doubt the sincerity of the developed countries with respect to
developing their technical capabilities and/or free trade. The commercial interests of the
developed countries dominate the TRIPS agreements.
Geographical indicators is another contested area of the TRIPS agreement. Article 22.1
defines them as “indications which identify a good as originating in the territory of a
member, or a region or locality in that territory, where a given quality, reputation or (some)
other characteristic of the good is (typical) to its geographic origin.” To be more specific,
consider the following. Neem trees can grow everywhere. One country calling it neem
cannot prevent others from using the same product (the only thing is that it may have to
be called something else and not neem; that is the trademark or copyright for the label alone
can be protected legally). In that case nobody can have any exclusive right. There is a
different viewpoint. Basmati rice was produced in some parts of India for centuries. Some
other country may now take this variety, produce it, and call it basmati as well. Does this
give them a right to exclusivity just because it has not been patented in India earlier? Two
issues have arisen.
• Can neem, basmati, and so on be considered as geographical indicators?
• Should patents and formal written documents, that are of much recent origin than
traditional knowledge transmitted orally through generations, be a requirement to
acknowledge intellectual property?
Can developing countries really afford the costs of doing this? Will it really add to their social
welfare?
There is no easy resolution. However, TRIPS acknowledges that they can be protected
through copyrights (again a formal registration). This prevents the use of a specific word like
basmati. However, it cannot prevent others from its production, use, or sales under a different
label so long as the consumer is not deceived into believing that the product is original
basmati.
Bioinformatics will also be covered under copyrights. Such rights prohibit copying or
reproduction of protected work. However, TRIPS introduces rental rights, i.e., the right to
authorize others to use it for a rent. It is difficult to monitor the use beyond the legitimate
first renter.
The advantages to developing countries, if any, as a result of the introduction of these
agreements, are not at all obvious. Some investigations in this direction will be outlined in
the next section.
50 Economics of Biotechnology

3.6 CONSEQUENCES OF PROTECTION


There is a fairly general acknowledgement that IPR protections can have far reaching
consequences for the economic functioning of markets. Prominent among them are the
following.
•Industrial concentration and monopoly power
•Prices of products
•Changes in social welfare
•Incentives for local firms to develop competitive research and product variety
•Discourage developmental work since generics cannot be introduced until the
patent expires
• Foreign direct investment
• Technology transfer
However, very limited information is available about many of these aspects. In particular,
• much of the literature deals with chemical based pharmaceutical industry and some
of it deals explicitly with the experiences of developing countries. Consequently,
it is difficult to assert that these results carry over to biotechnology patents as well
• the studies relating to agricultural biotechnology mostly relate to the U.S.A. A few
aspects are also pertinent in the context of less developed countries
This limited information will be presented in this section to provide a general direction to
this analysis.
Consider each of these aspects in turn.

Assume that a MNC succeeded in generating a new innovation. Suppose a patent is


granted. The initial impact of this is a monopoly and an increase in concentration. However,
it is expected that knowledge is freely available. Consequently, there is an expectation that
it stimulates others to work around it, create new methods and varieties, and patent them
in turn. The more the variety and patents (in a given therapeutic class or for a specific disease)
the greater the competition in the long run. This may materialize even before the expiry of
the original patent. But this may not happen. For,
• it may not be easy to invent around the patent (difficulty with scientific knowledge
itself). Schimmelpfennig et al. (2004) noted that it has been difficult to build up
varieties in cotton and corn (Bt varieties). However, varieties of soybean (RR va-
rieties) have been relatively easy
• a developing country may not have the scientific base and absorptive capacity to
create new knowledge even if it is possible. (see, for instance, Maria and Ramani
(2004).)
• successive introduction of varieties may have smaller market shares to make them
commercially viable; i.e., even the MNC will not find proliferation of varieties
profitable
IPRS and Patents 51

Lanjouw (1997) also observed that once a patent is granted in the country where the MNC
is located, all others, including potential international competitors, have access to it. As such
a patent granted for the same product is neither necessary nor sufficient for knowledge
diffusion and variety enhancing patents in less developed countries. In general, it is difficult
to determine the optimal product variety. Hence, it is not possible to clearly say that a specific
variety that materializes as a result of IPR protection is inefficient.
Studies, such as Subramanian (1995) and Watal (1995), considered the expected price
increases due to the monopoly power inherent in the grant of IPR protection. Based on
reasonable estimates of the elasticity of demand and marginal costs they found that the
expected price increase in drugs can be anywhere upto 75 percent of the pre-1995 prices.
However, as Watal and Mathai (1995) noted, it is difficult to attribute the entire low elasticity
of demand to IPR protection alone. For, the large chemical companies derive significant
market advantages from their marketing strategies, trademarks, and other promotional
campaigns as well.
It is widely believed that patent holders cannot charge monopoly prices as expected by
earlier studies. For, there exist several substitutable drug varieties in every therapeutic class.
Some of them may be older off patent drugs. Others may be produced under competitive
patents. One of the examples cited is that of quinolenes (antibiotics). This suggests that an
innovator has two types of competitors; producers of different rival products and firms
dealing in generic drugs. IPRs may give rise to competitive variety that restricts the price
increases that any one patent holder may be in a position to exploit. This is the general
position of the research based pharmaceutical MNCs. Three forces are at work in determining
the prices of such variety. First, suppose a patented product is sold at a high price. Then, the
demand curve for substitutable products shifts to the right. The rival firms then choose prices
to maximize their profits. They will be generally higher. This is the general conjecture in
Chamberlin’s monopolistic competition. Hence, larger variety may result in cascading price
increases rather than reduction. Second, in addition to the number of substitutable products
the elasticity of substitution between them also matters. In general, a lower elasticity of
substitution and therefore a lower elasticity of demand, has the effect of increasing prices.
Third, across international boundaries, where transfer pricing regulations apply, it is not
possible to maintain significantly different prices.
Fink (2000) found the variety effect of hypotensives to be price reducing. A similar result
was reported in the context of quinolenes by Chaudhuri et al. (2003). Litchenberg and Philipson
(2002) offered a general theoretical discussion of these substitution effects. However, it is
generally pointed out that the estimated price effects are quite sensitive to the elasticity of
substitution among varieties within a therapeutic class.
An important policy implication of these price changes was suggested in Chaudhuri et
al. (2003). When an IPR protection results in price increases the host country may impose price
controls. There is a limit to this because of the transfer pricing regulations. Suppose there is
a variety (or access) effect. Then, a compulsory licensing arrangement, to the extent it makes
variety possible, may be a superior policy from the viewpoint of the less developed country.
52 Economics of Biotechnology

Recall that a shift of some part of the consumer surplus to producers is the other expected
effect of IPR protection. In general, the results suggest that
• profits for the MNCs from developing countries may be a fairly significant share
of consumer welfare though the quantum is too small for the MNCs (relative to
their own home country) and also the costs of seeking and maintaining a patent
in the developing country
• the increase in product variety generally reduces the profit accruing to the MNC.
The more important point from Watal and Mathai (1995) is that these profits accrue to the
MNC and often repatriated to their parent country. Hence, an increased IPR protection, that
a less developed country offers, is unlikely to result in any increased R&D in that country.
The results with respect to welfare losses, measured by the deadweight loss (or the income
compensation necessary to maintain the same level of utility) exhibit similar results. Fink (2000)
also pointed out that “welfare losses are lower the more price elastic is overall demand in a
therapeutic group and higher the degree of substitutability among chemical entities. The latter
effect is relatively more pronounced … because the presence of a larger off-patent market
segment makes therapeutic competition more effective.” See also Chaudhuri et al. (2003).
Innovations pertaining to agricultural biotechnology are generally delivered through
seeds. Hence, IPR protection to seed companies may allow them to increase the prices of
seed. This may not be fully compensated by the reduction in other costs like spraying
pesticides. The increase in the equilibrium prices of crops and the corresponding welfare
losses depend on the shift in the supply curve. Moschini (2001) reported some attempts to
disentangle the various effects of IPRs.
It is often suggested that pharmaceutical firms in developing countries, like India and
elsewhere, have the technical capabilities to generate R&D. For, after all, in the absence of
patent protection, they could successfully create a market for generic drugs. Hence, it can be
expected that providing a strong patent protection will spur them into relevant R&D. As
Lanjouw (1997) pointed out, the large pharmaceutical firm may be compelled to do this if
the generics route is eliminated. However, there is a possibility that they will find it more
profitable to obtain technology from MNCs on the basis of license instead of their own R&D.
Similarly, the firms in the less developed countries may find it more advantageous to do
clinical testing work for the MNCs on an outsourcing basis. The risks involved in the large
amounts of investment as well as the difficulties of making suitable financial arrangements
may deter them from doing R&D work that will result in patents for them. Local development
of competitive drugs or development of drugs for locally specific diseases like malaria and
leprosy appear to be a remote prospect.
An obvious negative effect of strong IPR protection is more likely. For, even the R&D efforts
they undertook for the development of generic drugs would be lost. On the whole, the gains
to domestic pharmaceutical firms in less developed countries may turn out to be negative.
Observe that when a MNC is given patent protection in a less developed country the
profits accrue to the former. The claim is that this will spur MNCs to offer technology transfer
IPRS and Patents 53

to less developed countries through foreign direct investment. Similarly, it was suggested that
they may invest on R&D for local diseases. However, the MNCs generally feel that
• the profits are not large enough to be attractive (drug delivery at personal cost to
the patient rather than health insurance or national health schemes is one of the
deterrents)
• the presumed cost advantages in less developed countries (of cheap skilled labor
availability) is offset by other administrative bottlenecks and tariffs on import of
precision machinery etc.
• there are problems of infrastructure, information acquisition, commitment to con-
tracts (Maria and Ramani (2004)), and price controls
On balance, there is a general feeling that the less developed countries will lose, and
definitely not gain anything, by offering strong IPR protection to MNCs. If there is some
enterprising activity to begin with then IPRs may act as catalysts but they cannot, by themselves,
spur local firms to become more enterprising in the short run.

3.7 ISSUES OF CONCERN


There have been serious ethical and environmental concerns about the use of biotechnology
products especially with respect to food products. This resulted in a labeling and testing
regime for agricultural products traded across international boundaries. The precautionary
approach, viz., to reject a lot if an importing country is not satisfied about its safety, has been
put in place. However, this does not receive any specific mention in the TRIPS agreement.
The mandatory labeling of GMOs and GM derived products may turn out to be a powerful
incentive to develop handling and processing systems characterized by market segmentation
and/or identity preservation. Implementing an identity preservation system is costly because
to supply non-GM goods it is necessary to keep traditional crops segregated from the GM
varieties throughout the production and marketing system—through production, storage,
transportation, processing, and distribution. This may lead to a reduction in social welfare.
The problem is that this is also a non-tariff barrier under WTO and is illegal. But it cannot
be neglected.
The other issue is about differential pricing. To understand the simplest mechanics of its
operation reconsider Fig.1. In this diagram the monopoly is offering a quantity Ym at price
pm. However, from a social welfare viewpoint the most efficient output is Yw at price pw. To
keep the profit incentives in tact while attempting maximization of social welfare it is possible
to visualize market segmentation. For example, the regulator may insist that the patent holder
should supply the output YwYm at price pw. This restores welfare maximum. If the operation
of the market is within a country such segmentation may have to be achieved through the
physician network and suitable labeling and prescription. If the lower price segment is the
market in a less developed country the issues involved are different. First, under the transfer
pricing regulations a MNC cannot charge a price p1 in country 1 that is far below the lowest
price pI it charges in any other country. Hence, this arrangement may not be practical. In fact,
54 Economics of Biotechnology

it is possible that the MNC sets prices for all its segments keeping the global market demand
in perspective. This fails to maximize social welfare. Second, if the MNC is unwilling to adopt
differential pricing, a less developed country may force it to accept compulsory licensing to
a domestic firm that can deliver the output at a lower price. Third, even if such differential
pricing is possible, there is a necessity for institutional and legal mechanisms to ensure that
the product is not privately traded across the market segments. As noted earlier TRIPS
agreement does not specify any mechanism to achieve this.
In general, as the IPR commission acknowledged, it is expensive for less developed
countries to establish and operate elaborate IPR protections under the TRIPS agreement. It
may not be socially desirable to divert resources, which are already inadequate to take care
of education and health, toward administering a costly TRIPS agreement. Hence, several
dilemmas remain to be addressed.

3.8 MODIFICATIONS TO PATENT REGIME


Property rights generally consist of
• a right to own
• a right to use or rent it to others
• a right to modify
Implicitly such property rights allow the owner to exclude others from the use of such
property
• if he so chooses
• if others are not willing to pay the rent specified
The present day patent regime confers these property rights. However, note that such property
rights applied historically to final consumers. The question now is: should any or all these
rights apply to knowledge development as well? The existing patent regime appears to accept
this without any reservations.
However, Article 27.3 of the TRIPS agreement allows governments of sovereign countries
to exclude certain types of inventions from patents if national interests are at stake. That is,
one extreme form of reaction is to deny such patent rights altogether. This results in secrecy
and hinders knowledge diffusion.
In some cases, like the National Institute of Health in the U.S., the agency stipulates that
they will not allow certain types of discoveries of fundamental knowledge to be patented.
In the absence of an objective way of classifying different types of knowledge development
and specifying entitlements this remains subjective.
The question about financing such R&D is also pertinent. This may not be a serious issue
so long as adequate public funding is available for all such fundamental research. However,
over the years, there has been a reduction in the government involvement in biotechnology
R&D primarily because it did not contribute to defense needs in any major way. There is a
IPRS and Patents 55

possibility that R&D financed by such institutions would be inadequate. A further objection
may be raised even if adequate finances are provided. In particular, the contribution of any
one fundamental R&D to the value addition obtained from a final product of utility may far
exceed the cost of generating it. Therefore, any knowledge that contributes to such private
value addition in the ultimate analysis should be compensated adequately. Public funding
institutions may not be in a position to ascertain such value additions apriori let alone
compensate the innovators adequately. In other words, denying patents per se also hinders
knowledge generation and diffusion.
Rai (2005a) argues that there is a need for improving access by requiring publicly funded
scientists and research institutions to put data and certain types of research into the public
domain, or, at a minimum, to license them widely and non-exclusively for a reasonable fees.
Non-exclusivity reduces transaction costs and improves the range and quality of resulting
products. However, the question of deciding what constitutes reasonable fees cannot be
resolved objectively. Further, under the current patent regime, there is no way of compelling
private firms to accept non-exclusivity. This solution is also not adequate since private R&D
constitutes a major portion of biotechnology research.
Some individuals, that patented discoveries, voluntarily agreed to offer non-exclusive
access to their knowledge to everyone that needs to use it to move the knowledge forward.
The Cohen and Boyer patent for rDNA is one such example. There are two problems with
this approach. First, the problem of cost recovery must be resolved. One argument is that in
the context of biotechnology mere transfer of formal knowledge will not be sufficient to use
it. The scientist, that allows exclusive access to the knowledge he developed, may still charge
a consultancy fees for providing the informal knowledge. This may, in itself, be sufficient
especially when the use of knowledge spreads widely. Second, there is a possibility that only
the manufacturer of a final product sold on the market will usurp all the benefits of the chain
of discoveries. Hence, most innovators will be reluctant to use this approach.
Another alternative is to persuade the patent holder to offer his patented knowledge on
a collaborative basis or an open source mode. Rai (2005b) is depending on voluntary action
after granting exclusivity. The problem with this argument is as follows. Suppose a scientist
is granted a patent with the exclusivity clause in place and with a broad scope. Why should
he agree to share it for free or at low cost? In particular, a scientist, who is aware that the
final product developer is capturing the entire value added, will not accept this arrangement.
Rai (2005b) then falls back on the argument that markets in developing countries add very
low value to patents. Hence, she feels that innovators can easily be persuaded to provide
patented knowledge to them on a non-exclusive basis. But this creates a variety of new
problems if firms in developing countries, in turn, sell their products in industrial countries.
Hence, even this approach is not practical.
If none of the above solutions appear practically feasible the only option is to leave the
decision, to enforce exclusivity or leave the knowledge as a public good, to the scientists
themselves and/or the institutions that they belong to. However, the current patent regime
already made them feel that they can derive benefits by exploiting the monopoly power
56 Economics of Biotechnology

granted by knowledge patents. Consequently, it would be unrealistic to expect them to relent.


Rai and Eisenberg (2004) alluded to such attitudes of WARF (the Wisconsin Alumni Research
Foundation).
It would indeed be paradoxical to grant patent rights, with all its implications of property
rights, and then expect the patent holders to be persuaded that they should allow nonexclusive
use of their patent in the larger interest of social welfare.
For all practical purposes it is by now acknowledged that discoveries of knowledge need
protection by applying the utility doctrine with somewhat greater flexibility (not insisting on
utility to a consumer of final products). This appears to be a necessity in the context of
biotechnology. For, private individuals and firms, that finance such activities, cannot recover
the high costs of R&D otherwise. Exclusivity enables patent holders to claim royalties from
those that use their results of R&D. The exclusivity clause has become a hindrance to knowledge
diffusion though patent filing releases information in the public domain. Several observers
argued a case for narrowing patent rights to restore parity. See, for example, Abrol (2005),
Correa (2005), and Rai (2005a). However, as noted in the previous section, only Rai (2005a,b)
has some analysis of alternatives.
Two situations are conceivable. First, there may be a cumulative chain of ‘n’ inventions
before a final product emerges. Second, a new R&D effort, perhaps at the downstream level,
may require knowledge embodied in ‘n’ earlier patented innovations that are not interrelated
in the above sense. The requirements of knowledge diffusion in these two cases are somewhat
different.
In the first case each stage of invention can be considered as a different marketable
product. The patent holder may then be allowed to negotiate a license to a user at the
downstream level and extract rents based on the perceptions of the two parties regarding the
value added in that particular use. Similarly, he may grant licenses to many firms pursuing
different types of applications and developments. However, in line with the conventional
patent regime, the patent holder’s rights should be deemed to have been exhausted after the
first stage license. This reduces the burden of negotiating a license with all the early down
stream innovators.
The main advantage of this approach is in allowing faster diffusion of knowledge. It also
reduces the burden of transaction costs on the final stage innovator. Clearly, the patent holder
at each stage may negotiate the license based on his perception of value that his knowledge
contributes. The only disadvantage is that early stage innovators may not be in a position
to assess the ultimate market value of their innovation. Will the patent holder not grant
licenses to competitors pursuing the development of the same marketable product? There
may be some short run difficulties. However, long term reputation will be at stake if such
moral hazard persists. Hence, it is unlikely in the long run.
A second approach is more practical. Begin with the observation that the innovator at the
final product stage can recover costs when a marketable final product is available. The
licensing contract for upstream knowledge is similar to subcontracts for parts and franchise
bidding in any other industrial context. Confronted with risks in the ultimate product market
IPRS and Patents 57

the upstream firm has two choices. First, choose the rents ex ante to resolve the risk. This
is somewhat similar to the model alluded to above. Second, wait for the risk to be resolved
ex post and claim returns accordingly. More often than not, the second choice is more efficient
and it can be implemented if knowledge about the market is not difficult to verify. This
suggests the following modification to the patent regime. Suppose that the system of patenting
knowledge is continued with two conditions. First, each of the early stage innovators will be
under obligation to provide the knowledge on a non-exclusionary basis. Second, the entire
chain of related innovators must be compensated if and when later stage R&D results in a
marketable product. This accelerates knowledge diffusion while preserving the appropriability
of intermediate discoveries of knowledge. The practical problem of apportioning the eventual
benefits among them can be resolved by making payments proportional to the costs incurred
at each stage of R&D development. This generally results in recovering more than the costs
involved and closer to the contribution of any one aspect of knowledge to the ultimate value.
Hence, the objections raised in the context of public funding of R&D will not arise.
The patent application must normally specify the territory that the applicant considers
his own and thus exclude others from it. Hence, the following subtle points can be introduced.
First, he may be required to spell out the developments for which the use of knowledge will
be allowed on a non-exclusionary basis. Two examples can be offered. (a) The knowledge
under consideration is not known to result in any marketable product either within the scope
of the patent or outside of it. (b) In some cases there may not be any market for early
knowledge developments because utility is not obvious. Second, there may be some parts of
scientific knowledge that he considers far removed from a final product. In such a case he
may be asked to specify the parts of knowledge that he will exclude unless a payment is made.
Note that the second model proposed here is quite general. It is applicable even in the
case where the ‘n’ upstream innovations are not cumulatively related. Further, as noted
above, this model may turn out to be superior even in the context of cumulative knowledge
developments.
However, in general, it must be noted that the new model will be usable only if the patent
application contains information about all the prior patented knowledge utilized in the
downstream development. It is also necessary for every scientist, at the intermediate stages
of development, to declare the costs of their R&D. From an operational viewpoint there may
be a necessity for some institutional mechanism to ensure that payments are properly made
and redress grievances if they arise.
One objection to the new scheme may still arise. Note that under the present patent regime
a scientist can claim payments as early as possible. What then is the incentive for him to wait
until some final product of utility is marketed? Two points may be recorded as possible
answers to this question. First, it is well known, from the economic theory of incomplete
contracts, that such ex ante resolution is inefficient under conditions of risk. Second, under
the present patent regime there will be fewer users and/or uses of knowledge that the patent
holder developed. This is primarily due to the costs that must be paid before the value is
realized and the extensive transaction costs. When the new model is in operation, there will
58 Economics of Biotechnology

be widespread knowledge diffusion and a better chance of value enhancement. Hence, the
losses due to the time lags may be more than compensated. However, it must be acknowledged
that this is an empirical matter so that any apriori judgement about the superiority of one
over the other may not be warranted.
On the whole, as in the established practice, accepting full property rights for products
of utility can be justified. However, they should not apply to at all stages of knowledge
development. Otherwise the pious hope that patents will result in extensive knowledge
diffusion will not materialize.
Investment and Financing 59

Chapter 4

INVESTMENT AND FINANCING

4.1 THE ISSUES


In the context of the biotechnology industry R&D activities are of several types. Prominent
R&D activities are in areas like
• basic scientific discoveries of cell structure, protein synthesis
• the process of transforming laboratory research into marketable products
• clinical tests of drugs or field trials of crops
• the manufacturing and market release of final products
The first two phases of biotechnology industry are such that many new NBFs do not have any
developed and readily marketable product.
It was noted in chapter 2 that the primary consideration, of a NBF considering an alliance
with a university scientist, is the number of patents he has and how active he is in current
scientific developments. This will determine the usefulness and the likely success of the NBF.
It also defines its ability to convince would be investors about its potential to generate the
requisite finances. Similarly, a NBF with many patents on industrial processes will be an
advantage to a large firm forging links with it. In other words, when considering the R&D
decision at the earlier stages, where there is no tangible marketable output, the main
consideration is the market value of its assets. This may be purely a valuation by the accountants
or the capital market.
The products of the NBF are essentially scientific knowledge with little or no established
reputation and experience high rates of obsolescence. They also lack tangible assets. As a result
their growth depends primarily on personal savings (and may be angel capital from friends).
The government recognizes the social value of such discoveries and comes to their rescue by
60 Economics of Biotechnology

providing finances, facilities, tax subsidies and so on. Later stage firms, or mature NBFs, derive
their finances from conventional sources comprising of
• venture capital sources
• commercial banks and financial institutions
• capital markets
• private equity placements
• investment from foreign MNCs
At higher levels of the biotechnology value chain, involving manufacture and distribution
of marketable products targeted to specific consumer needs, the innovative knowledge must
be embedded in physical capital. Investments in R&D and physical capital will be
complementary assets at this stage of development. Private biotechnology firms determine
both of them to maximize the discounted cashflows that they generate by utilizing the market
to conduct the sale of their products.
One important factor in generating the cashflows is the nature of market demand. Consider
agricultural biotechnology. The seed industry, especially the one dealing with GM seeds, is
highly concentrated. They, however, have competition from conventional varieties. It should
also be noted that the conventional varieties, over time, have been adapted to local agro climatic
conditions whereas the currently available GM varieties are not equally adaptable. These
features make the demand for GM seeds somewhat elastic despite the monopoly achieved
through IPR protection. Another important feature of the seed industry is the extension services.
In general, the private companies, that sell GM seeds, offer assistance regarding the application
of pesticides, herbicides, and so on. But the farmer has to pay for these. Further, the assistance
is generally not site specific. On the contrary, the government funded agricultural extension
services work closely with the farmer and offer specific assistance to each farmer. The demand
for GM seeds depends on these arrangements as well.
Several factors determine the demand for GM crops and foods produced from them. The
most important among them is the consumer resistance to GM crops. Many still prefer non-
GM varieties. The demand for these varieties is, however, depending on the cost of labeling
GM products. To a large extent this problem is affecting the demand for GM crops across
national boundaries as well. Price controls and support prices have always been a determinant
of demand. The differences in the marketing and distribution channels also contribute to this.
Pharmaceutical products are subject to a different set of problems.
• The patent protection for drugs is far more stringent compared to GM foods
• There is much greater monopoly power
• However, there are conventional chemical technology based drugs in many thera-
peutic classes. This variety, along with some alternatives in the biotechnology area,
offer competition. This is especially valid in countries like the U.S.A. where even
alternative formulations have been granted independent patents. See, for instance,
the examples in Correa (2001).
• In the less developed countries the drug market experiences significant price controls.
• There is no meaningful national health scheme or insurance cover against illness
in several countries. The patients must pay for the expensive drugs from their
Investment and Financing 61

incomes. This reduces the demand considerably. The situation is better wherever
national health schemes cover at least some expenses of health care. So it is with
insurance.
The basic point is that patterns of drug delivery have a fundamental bearing on the demand
for pharmaceutical products.
The cost implication of R&D and the production of the resulting high quality products are
equally important in determining the growth of biotechnology firms. For, fundamentally, a
discovery is useful only if it results in the reduction of cost of delivering a unit of product of
given quality. The high costs and risks associated with the development of biotechnology
necessitated public policies and spending to ensure that socially desirable innovations
materialize.
As noted earlier, R&D in biotechnology products and the actual production of specific
output depend on the financial arrangements. In addition to the sources mentioned above, the
following have also been significant.
• Intercorporate and private placement of equity holdings tend to cushion some of
the risks of these investments
• Venture capital has also been active at this higher level of the value chain
However, it should be noted that public funding of activities at this stage of production are
much less compared to the first two phases of the development of biotechnology. In general,
even public institutions have been encouraged to raise finances by licensing their patented
technology to private firms.
The investments in basic R&D and later stages of biotechnology will now be examined
with these aspects in perspective. As Cohen and Levin (1989) noted, there is no justification to
exclusively emphasize the effect of market structure as the dominant determinant of R&D
and capital investments in the biotechnology sector.

4.2 ROLE OF PUBLIC INVESTMENT


Most technologies, including the internet development, have four distinct characteristics.
• The initial developments have been sponsored and financed by the government
because they have some implications for defense
• The published formal knowledge (in some cases through patent filing) is adequate
for others to reproduce it and create materials to use it. In particular, there was no
specific necessity for the original scientist to participate in the transfer of knowl-
edge. That is, the requirement of informal knowledge is minimal or non-existent
• There is no necessity for transfer of any physical materials or laboratory tools along
with the knowledge
• Most of them are directly related to products of utility to consumers
Against this backdrop the universities, where knowledge development is initiated, trained
young scientists in the new discoveries and knowledge. The private firms then used this pool of
62 Economics of Biotechnology

talent to implement the technological breakthrough. In sum, the development of technological


knowledge has been considered as a public good and transferred to the private firms through
the educational process. In a few cases, like the agriculture extension services, even public research
organizations participated in the development and transfer of the requisite R&D.
Biotechnology development, at least in the initial phases, has been different in all these
respects. In addition, much of the R&D remains in the hands of private firms due to the absence
of any utility for defense purposes. However, there has been a significant involvement of the
public sector in basic R&D in countries like Germany, Japan, and India due to several
institutional and cultural considerations. In particular, the public sector had a role in
• setting up research laboratories and sponsoring research
• transfer of knowledge to the private firms
• finances and other incentives to reduce risks
See, for instance, Giesecke (2000) and Lehrer and Asakawa (2004). One of the important
questions pertain to the relative proportions of the private and public R&D. In addition to
this quantitative dimension the major issue is about the areas of application that would be
pertinent to each of these sectors of activity.
The following framework may therefore be utilized to examine some of the issues
involved in the efficient transfer of public scientific knowledge to private firms. Initially
a private firm identifies promising R&D activities. However, it does not have the
scientific knowledge, considers the risks too high, and/or appropriability too low. The
private firm expects the government to resolve the risk before they undertake further
development (bioprocessing for instance) and production. Hence, it is possible to view
the government as a partner in the development of R&D after the private firm spots
some worthwhile activity. Clearly, the possibility that the public sector initiates the
necessary action for the private firms to follow it up at an appropriate time is also a real
possibility. Precedence may not be the essence of creating socially beneficial R&D. See,
for example, Khush (2004).
Another important feature of the development of biotechnology is the emergence of the
new biotechnology firms (NBFs). They have been the essential link between specialized
research institutions (either public or private) and the large pharmaceutical and seed companies
that manufacture and market the final products. The basic reasons are as follows. No private
firm has adequate scientific manpower or the laboratory tools to undertake the more
fundamental activities in the early phases of their development. Perforce they must be
developed and incubated in specialized research institutions (either public or private) and
transferred to private firms through appropriate organizational mechanisms. These
technologies are also such that a formal transfer of blueprints (or the disclosure at the patent
filing stage) is generally inadequate to make efficient use of the results of R&D. The transfer
of informal knowledge, made possible only through close interaction with the scientists, has
become a compulsion. Irrespective of the composition chosen, the government and its
institutions had to play a crucial role in providing arrangements for technology transfer
between various actors in the network.
Investment and Financing 63

Hence, it should be acknowledged that developing network organizations, for the transfer
of informal knowledge in their functioning, will be critical. Realistically, when private and/
or public firms depend on the transfer of informal knowledge, they learn to identify
appropriate network members and they in turn learn to work in teams. This process results
in organizational learning, spillovers, and concomitant improvements in technology and
productivity.
There have been two other reasons for the emergence of the NBFs. First, most of the
developments of biotechnology are capital intensive. The institutions undertaking the basic
R&D generally do not have access to requisite finances. The NBFs, with their more significant
capabilities in scaling up technology for commercialization, have better access to venture capital
and other sources of finance. Second, there have been significant risks in R&D at the present
stage of biotechnology development. In particular, many research findings may fail at the
bioprocessing or the regulatory stage so that cost recovery is not commercially possible. The
NBFs act as a buffer between R&D institutions and the large firms and absorb the risks that
are intrinsic to progress in biotechnology.
For many years, knowledge developed in R&D laboratories (both private and public) was
considered a public good and was accessible to anyone that wished to utilize it and move it to
the market. However, after the 1980s, the patent regime allowed patenting of such knowledge
and discoveries from R&D. Further, public organizations in many countries have been
encouraged to recover the costs of R&D through contracts and licensing. Creating an
atmosphere for R&D and its efficient diffusion through patenting and other public policy
measures has also been an important feature of the developments in biotechnology.
In sum, public policy with respect to the biotechnology sector consists of the following.
• The government may create and/or support public institutions that undertake such
research
• Public R&D may precede private R&D in order to create the atmosphere for the
later to flourish
• Public institutions may offer agricultural extension services to reduce costs
• The government may finance such private R&D
• Public policy may nurture venture capital and foreign direct investment
• Public financing of national health schemes may augment the demand for medi-
cines and their appropriability
• The government may create a suitable patent and IPR regime
Ramani (2002) has a perceptive observation. As she pointed out, the above approaches to
public policy focused on two ends of commercialization, viz., public research organizations
and final product manufacturers. The effort was to retain the decision making autonomy of
each of the institutions involved, to the extent possible, and hope that formal interaction
between them will develop to benefit society at large. This was also noted in Raina (2003).
However, as Ramani pointed out, “the indispensable intermediate link to (translate) scientific
knowledge into technological competence was largely skipped”.
64 Economics of Biotechnology

4.3 R&D IN SCIENTIFIC KNOWLEDGE


The simplest formal model of R&D expenditures in the early stages of biotechnology
development proceeds as follows. Let E be the expenditure on R&D at any point of time t. To
begin with assume that a private firm is financing the entire expenditure. This is usually
designated as an input measure of R&D. It would be equally plausible to conceptualize the
number and strength of patents obtained by the firm as a measure of R&D. This will be the
output measure of R&D. The fundamental nature of the analysis will not change materially
irrespective of which measure is employed. Hence, the rest of the analysis will be based on the
input measure.
The scientific knowledge so discovered accumulates over time. Such R&D may be useful
in accelerating the nature of discoveries as well because each successive discovery is built on
past knowledge and experiences. This common observation is reiterated in Cohen and Levin
(1989). Denote by R the stock of this accumulated R&D. It is generally acknowledged that new
discoveries make some existing knowledge obsolete. This is the spirit of Schumpeterian creative
destruction. Bottezzi et al. (2001, p.1164) summarized this process in the following way. When
a new innovation enters the market it is rapidly diffused throughout the market. Invariably
this is achieved through a displacement of older varieties where they exist. It also spurs
competitive R&D in generating competing varieties, e.g., equivalent drugs in the same
therapeutic class. It is important to recognize that such changes tend to occur before the patent
on the original discovery expires. However, the rate of decay of R depends on many factors.
Assume that εR; ε > 0 represents the reduction in the stock of R at any point of time. The
trajectory of R over time can therefore be represented by
dR/dt = E – εR
The firm can be expected to choose E at each point of time so as to maximize the present
discounted value of the valuation that accountants and/or other interested parties assign to
the stock of R&D of the firm.
The valuation of R is subject to diminishing returns for the following reasons.
• An increase in R generally indicates that the firm has already appropriated most
of the profitable investment opportunities. The incremental value expected from
further R&D will consist of activities that yield lower returns.
• As the level of R&D increases, and the NBF becomes larger, it requires extensive
network relationships. Due to organizational differences between the constituents
and associated coordination problems it must be expected that there will be dimin-
ishing returns to increases in R.
• A large NBF may develop greater monopoly power. However, in line with the
Spence formula, it becomes difficult for it to extract all the value that the potential
users of the technology associate with it.
• An increase in R also suggests that the firm has used up most of the financial
resources available to invest in R&D. Hence, further R&D can be taken up only by
Investment and Financing 65

using more expensive sources of finance. This reduces the additional value gener-
ating potential of R&D.
• Much of R&D, in particular, activities related to biotechnology, is very specific to
the firm in the initial stages when a patent is in force. If there is any failure it
becomes very difficult for the firm to recover its finances due to the low liquidation
value of these specific assets.
See, for instance, Correa (2001) and Sporleder and Moss (2004).
Hence, the gross value addition from a stock R of R&D can be written as
V = Rα; 0 ≤ α ≤ 1
This has been achieved at a cost E at time t. Therefore, the net value addition is
V = Rα – E
The choice problem for the firm is therefore to define E as a function of time in such a way as
to maximize

∫ e–rt (Rα – E) dt
0

subject to
dR/dt = E – εR
This problem in calculus of variations can be solved by Pontryagin’s maximum principle. It
results in a choice of E such that
αRα–1 = r + ε
Note that a net unit increase in R necessitates an increase in E equal to (1 + ε/r) where
0
– ∫ e–rtε dt = ε/r
–∞

represents the depreciation of all earlier R&D stock. Hence, the interest cost (or, cost per
unit increase in R) will be r+ε. This is usually designated as the user cost of R&D stock.
Similarly, αRα–1 is the increase in the value of the R&D stock per unit increase in it.
Hence, the choice of R, and consequently E, is optimal if
αRα–1 = r + ε
Following Jorgenson (1963) this can be written as
R/V = α/(r + ε)
This way of expressing the solution suggests that the optimal R
• increases with the gross value V that the firm desires to achieve
• increases if the productivity (or the value generating potential) a of R is higher
66 Economics of Biotechnology

• decreases with an increase in the user cost. In particular, if the firm experiences faster
decay of its R&D stock due to competitive pressures, it will tend to reduce R
• decreases with an increase in the discount rate (this is a reflection of the willingness
on the part of the entrepreneur to wait for a longer time to recover the value)
Assume that the government provides IPR protection to all such investments. One of the
consequences of this policy is that ε will fall because competitive imitation is no longer possible.
The only effective competition is by creating a new technique that serves the same function
and get it patented. Secondly, it may be easier to extract the possible gross value relatively
easily. It may then be expected that α will decrease. Thirdly, the firm may no longer be impatient
with respect to recovering value as soon as possible. For, it has the life of the patent available
to it to get the money back. That is, r itself may be lower. These aspects of the effects of IPR
protection were noted in Alfranca and Huffman (2003) and Sporleder and Moss (2004). All
these forces tend to increase the R&D expenditures that a firm undertakes.

4.4 RISKS OF R&D


It is generally observed that the R&D investments in biotechnology are highly risky.
Coupled with high investment this risk inhibits firms from undertaking investment. This can
be elucidated in the following manner. Suppose the private firm spends E on R&D. Let p be
the probability of success. Clearly, the expenditure adds to the stock of R&D only if it is a
success. Hence, the expected change in R can be represented by
dR/dt = pE – εR
Suppose the firm chooses E so as to

Max ∫ e–rt [Ra – E]dt
0

Subject to
dR/dt = pE – εR
The optimal value of R will then be
R = αpV/(r + ε)
p < 1 indicates that the cumulative expenditure on R&D will decrease.
It is therefore possible to view equity investments by venture capital and capital markets
in general as a sort of seed money that enables the firm to assess the probability of success.
The private sector may then make the rest of the investment with the probability p of success
that it identifies. This role of the equity capital can be incorporated into the above model in the
following way. Suppose the capital market invests (1–f)E on R&D that enables the private
firm to find out the probability of success of the R&D effort it is trying out. See, for instance,
Investment and Financing 67

Allen and Gale (1999). The private firm makes an investment with a probability p that it
discovers. The expected value of the private investment is therefore pfE. The total expenditure
on R&D is therefore [1 – f(1–p)]E. The private firm chooses E so as to

Max ∫ e–rt [Rα – pfE] dt
0
subject to
dR/dt = [1 – f(1–p)]E – εR
The optimal choice of R is therefore given by
R = αV [1 – f(1 – p)] / (r + ε)pf
It may now be verified that the expression
e = [1 – f(1 – p)] / pf
is a monotonic decreasing function in f. Therefore, it can be concluded that private R&D
increases with equity spending.
The above analysis does not take into account the possibility that
• too much (1 – f) may discourage the private firm from making any R&D investment
• there will be a reduction in the proportion of benefits that the private firm can
appropriate because, having made some investment, the capital market will not
allow the private firm to appropriate all the benefit.
However, despite these limitations, this analysis indicates that there is another channel through
which equity placements can affect private spending on R&D.
One further observation is in order. As noted in an earlier chapter, biotechnology
innovations are not always cumulative. In particular, the discoverer of one protein does not
have any specific advantage in discovering another. The net value of R&D expenditure may
only be
V = AEα – E
The optimal R&D expenditure will then be
E = (Aα)1/(1–α)
An increase in α is still conducive to an increase in E.
Note that the fraction f of investment may be government spending. The rest of the analysis is
still valid.
Some disadvantages of such government policy may now be recorded.
• The government may put limits on the type of R&D undertaken as well as control
the prices of the resulting products sold on the market. This was noted in
Kalaitzandonakes (1999).
• The policy makers experience information asymmetry with respect to the probabil-
ity of success of a venture and the expected market value of the innovation. This
68 Economics of Biotechnology

may make them reluctant to finance some otherwise worthwhile investments. See,
for example, Ferreira and Brooks (2000) and Lerner et al. (2003).
• Recent policies, of the government, allow public institutions, through whom financ-
ing is channeled, to claim royalties from the revenue generated. This limits the
motivation to increase R. See, Lerner et al. (2003).
In the context of biotechnology the failure may be at later stages like bioprocessing and
regulatory approvals. In other words, the firm may spend E and create R but recover Rα with
only a probability p. Consider the problem of

Max ∫ e–rt (pRα – E) dt
0
subject to
dR/dt = E – εR
This results in an optimal R given by
R/V = pα/(r + ε)
With this in perspective the government may agree to share (1–f)E of expenditure to encourage
R&D. Such a public policy results in the choice of
R/V = α/f(r + ε)
Clearly, public policies of this nature also assist in improving the R&D culture of the firm.
Note that the institutional arrangement, like patents and providing monopoly power to
the firm, may adequately compensate the firm. This alternative is perhaps superior in
practice.
Another dimension of risk is specific to agricultural biotechnology. GM products are new
to the consumers. There is some resistance especially with respect to genetically modified
food. That is, there is a problem with the appropriability of GM products in the eventual
product market. In such a case p represents the degree of appropriability. Hence, the
government may spend (1–f)E to augment the market demand for the products of the private
firm. A case in point, as noted in Just and Heuth (1993), may be the public financing of national
health schemes meant to augment the demand for medicines. It is obvious that the above
analytical argument will hold even in this context.
Further, the availability of and preference for conventional non-GM products persists.
Competition on the market for GM products is from such non-GM varieties as well. As
noted in the above context, a part of the expenditure E may then be on marketing of
biotechnology. However, granting a patent and monopoly rights would be a more efficient
alternative. For, it can limit competition from other GM products and imitative generic
products. The resulting increase in appropriability mitigates the difficulties associated with
the risk of a low value of p.
Investment and Financing 69

4. 5 COMPLEMENTARY R&D
In the early stages of the development of biotechnology, especially due to the high costs of
R&D, any one scientist or a private research institution is developing only a part of the
knowledge necessary to move towards a final product. In most cases, the knowledge about
one of these aspects is necessary to create the next stage of the technology. Knowledge diffusion
and progress in R&D slows down if such fragments of knowledge remain a secret. However,
many scientists preferred such secrecy and developing complementary R&D on their own.
For, at least until the 1980s, patenting knowledge, that does not directly result in utility to a
final consumer, was not possible. The effect of this approach and alternatives to it can be
analyzed in the following manner.
Let Ej (j = 1, 2) represent the expenditures on these two activities and let Rj (j=1,2 ) represent
the stocks of R&D built up in these two directions. As before, it can be expected that
dR1/dt = E1 – ε1R1
dR2/dt = λE2 – ε2R2
This formulation presumes that λ < 1 is the efficiency with which the first firm can undertake
R&D related to the complementary knowledge. Similarly, the expected market value of the
innovations will be
V = θR1αR2β
Note that the private firm decided to pursue R&D regarding R2 while maintaining secrecy
with respect to R1. It is therefore vulnerable to competitive pressure. For, someone else may
discover R1 in the meantime and patent it. Hence, it may be in a position to retrieve the expected
value addition only with some probability θ. It is also possible that the developments will fail
at the regulatory stage. This risk can also be included in the specification of θ.
The private firm therefore chooses E1 and E2 so as to

Max ∫ e–rt (θR1αR2β – E1 – E2) dt
0
subject to the above two differential equations. Clearly, the optimal choices will be
R1/V = θα/(ε1 + r)
R2/V = θβλ/(ε + r)
One alternative available to the firm, when it recognizes complementarily, is to enter a
private network arrangement and choose an optimal contract for sharing gains. An agreement
of this nature is feasible if the commercial secrets can be reined in within the partners of the
network.
Assume that one private firm develops R1, and contracts with a second firm to develop R2. Let
s be the share of the accruing value paid to the first firm. The optimal choice of the first firm
70 Economics of Biotechnology

will be
R1/V = sα/(ε + r)
Similarly, the choice of the second firm, which is the most efficient in developing R2 and
hence λ = 1, becomes
R2/V = (1 – s)β/(ε2 + r)
This contractual agreement results in a higher level of R1 if s > θ. Similarly, R2 will be higher if s< 1
– θλ. Hence, specialization and networking will be an efficient organizational arrangement
whenever θ < s < 1 – θλ. This mechanism is superior whenever θ and/or λ is small.
However, there may be a holdup and inefficiency if the share s demanded by the first firm
is outside these limits. Private network arrangements may then be replaced by the government
research laboratory working on R1 and providing it to the private firm that develops R2. The
advantage of this agreement is that even low values of s may be acceptable. The recent
experience of most of the countries is that the government is encouraging such contractual
agreements. Public policy is then limited to the specification of the limits on s with social
welfare in perspective.
However, note that government policy, amounting to merely allowing patent rights for
fragments of knowledge may be adequate to induce private firms to enter into network
arrangements that generate efficient R&D of complementary knowledge.
The existence of risk at various levels, as noted in the previous section, necessitates
government policies to encourage bearing such risks. The analytical details will be very similar.
The above analysis assumed that the transfer of formal knowledge regarding R1 is sufficient
to proceed with the development of R2. However, it is well known that transfer of informal
knowledge has a critical role in biotechnology development. This will be considered in detail
in the sequel.

4.6 AGRICULTURAL EXTENSION SERVICES


One of the most important features of the network relationships in biotechnology is the
transfer of informal knowledge. In the context of agricultural biotechnology this takes the
form of extension services. Of late several private seed companies have been providing such
services to the farmers. However, traditionally the public sector institutions were entrusted
with this role. From an operational viewpoint it consists of the accumulation, over time, of the
expertise in the use of seeds that embody new technologies with the hope that the farmer will
eventually have enough knowledge in the use of such technologies. The degree of risk of
failure is not as severe in the context of agricultural extension services.
The basic issue related to R&D at this stage of bioprocessing is the accumulation of the
stock of informal knowledge in the use of a new technology that has already been established
through an earlier stage of R&D. Let R be the stock of R&D available for transfer. The farmer
generally spends an amount E at time t to use the seeds that embody such technologies. Further,
Investment and Financing 71

when he gets the knowledge about extension services, he has to pay an additional amount P.
The accumulated knowledge S can be expressed as
dS/dt = γP – ηS
and the value of output generated at time t will be
V = EαSβ
Hence, the farmer can be expected to choose E and P to maximize the present discounted
value of net returns

∫ e–rt (EαSβ – E – P) dt
0

subject to the above differential equation.


The optimal choices will therefore be
E = αV
βV/S = (r + η)/γ
Hence, it follows that
S/V = βγ/(r + η)
Note that a constraint S ≤ S can be imposed on the maximization problem. In that case, P will
*

be equal to S* once it is attained.


The question that should be addressed is: will government provision of extension services
improve the rate of accumulation of S? Consider the choice problem of the farmer. He now
maximizes
F = EαSβ – E
by choosing E such that
αEα–1Sβ = 1
Hence, E = αV and substitution yields
V = αα/(1–α)Sβ/(1– α)
Hence, the problem for the government is to choose P in such a way as to

Max ∫ e–rt [αα/(1–α) Sβ/(1–α) – P] dt
0

subject to
dS/dt = γP – ηS
The optimal choice satisfies the equation
S/V = βγ/(1 – α)(r + η)
Clearly, since 0 < α < 1, this quantity is larger than the farmer’s choice when he is paying a private
firm for extension services. Hence, public provision of extension services helps accumulate S faster.
72 Economics of Biotechnology

4.7 BIOPROCESSING
One of the distinctive features of biotechnology is the necessity to provide informal
knowledge in the process of transferring scientific R&D to a higher stage of development.
The new biotechnology firms (NBFs) undertake bioprocessing based on basic patented
scientific knowledge obtained from university scientists and other research laboratories.
There is no assurance of success at bioprocessing and regulatory stages despite the
accumulation of informal knowledge. Assume, to begin with, that the scientist or the private
firm expects the bioprocessing firm to pay an amount P to offer such informal knowledge.
However, the efficiency of the bioprocessing firm in assimilating it cannot be instantaneous.
It is more realistic to expect such a firm to accumulate the stock of requisite knowledge over
time and with repeated use of knowledge transferred to it. Let γ represent the efficiency
with which the firm can assimilate such informal knowledge and assume that the stock of
knowledge decays at a rate η. Then, the net addition to S at time t will be determined by
dS/dt = γP – ηS
There will be a specific amount E of expenditure on conducting the biotechnology activity
itself. However, the activities are subject to the risk of failure. Hence, only a fraction pE of the
expenditure contributes to value addition. The other aspect that needs attention is the problem
of acquisition of patented knowledge. As the number of such fragments, that need to be
acquired, increases the license fees, either upfront or royalty payments, increases. This reduces
the actual amount of E available to biprocessing itself. The fraction p captures this aspect as
well. The gross value addition may therefore be written as
Vg = (pE)αSβ
The problem for the firm is then to

Max ∫ e–rt [(pE)αSβ – E – P] dt
0

subject to
dS/dt = γP – ηS
The solution to this problem is
E = αPαV, and
S/V = βpαγ/(r+η) where
V = EαSβ
Clearly, some government intervention, to reduce costs and improve recovery rate, is in order.
It may be argued that patented knowledge, at least some fundamental aspects of it that have
widespread application, should be made available for non-exclusive license at no cost or for a
predefined fixed payment. In fact, the Cohen and Boyer rDNA patent is made available on
this basis. Such an adjustment, apart from decreasing costs, allows faster diffusion of
knowledge.
Investment and Financing 73

Suppose, on the other hand, that the government offers to spend (1–f)E so that the firm
can explore the probability p of success before investing fE. The solution to the problem will
now be
E/V = α [1 – (1 – p)f]α/pf, and
S/V = βγ [1 – (1 – p)f]α/(r + η)
It is readily apparent that such government interventions improve the biprocessing activity
and hence knowledge diffusion.
For the sake of analytical generality it must be acknowledged that some amount of R&D
and discovery of new knowledge is implied even at the bioprocessing stage. In other words,
the expenditure E contributes to the development of R&D. The stock of R&D then contributes
to the value of the firm. This modification does not change the results in any fundamental
way.

4.8 PHYSICAL CAPITAL


Consider the latter stages of the biotechnology value chain where the firm is producing
output for a final consumer market. The choice of the optimal stock of capital is somewhat
analogous to the above. Let
K = stock of physical capital at any time t
It will be assumed that this deteriorates at some rate δ. Suppose
I = gross investment in physical capital at time t
Then, the net addition to the stock of capital is given by
dK/dt = I – δK
The output from the use of this capital can be represented as
Y = Kβ ; 0 ≤ β ≤ 1
Let the market price per unit of Y be unity for purposes of analytical simplicity. Similarly, let
q = price per unit of I
The firm therefore chooses K to maximize the present discounted value of cashflows. That is,

Max ∫ e–rt [Kβ – qI] dt
0
subject to
dK/dt = I – δK
The optimal value of K is given by
K = βY/ q(r + δ)
if Y is the output target of the firm. As before the user cost of capital is q(r+δ).
74 Economics of Biotechnology

One pertinent question is the following. Suppose the firm has a monopoly power in the
market for Y. This may be, for instance, a result of patent protection. What will be the effect on
the optimal choice of K? To answer this question let the demand curve for Y be written as
Y = p–η, where
η = elasticity of demand
Then, the revenue accruing to the firm is
Revenue = Kβ(1–1/η) = Kθ (say)
where θ = β(1–1/η) < β
because η > 1 in the operationally relevant range. The optimal K then becomes
Km = θY1–1/η/ q(r + δ)
This quantity is definitely less than the optimal K obtained earlier under the assumption of a
competitive market.
It can also be shown that this quantity is less than the welfare maximizing value of K. For,
recall, from the Spence formula, that
Kθ = revenue = (1 – 1/η) welfare
Consider the welfare maximizing choice of K. It is such as to

Max ∫ e–rt [ ηKθ/(η–1) – qI] dt
0

subject to
dK/dt = I – δK
The optimal value of K then satisfies the equation
ηKθ–1/(η–1) = q(r + δ)/θ
Therefore, it follows that
Kw = ηθY1–1/η/(η – 1) q(r + δ) > Km
for all relevant values of η.
The usual claim made in favor of patent protection is that the firm will use the monopoly
profits to increase the stock of capital. However, the above formulation does not justify such a
claim. Surely, the relevant monopoly power, if any, is not reflected in the elasticity of demand
per se.
The conventional result can, however, be rescued if an increase in K allows the firm to
appropriate the market by shifting the demand curve to the right. Replace the demand curve
by
Y = p–ηKφ,
where φ = degree of appropriability
Investment and Financing 75

The revenue will now be


Revenue = Kθ + φ/η = Kψ (say),
where ψ = θ + φ/η
The optimal choice of K is therefore
Km = ψY1–1/η+φ/βη/q(r + δ)
> βY/q(r + δ)
if φ > β. In other words, there will be at least some values of φ such that the monopoly increases
its investment in physical capital. The problem of appropriability remains if φ < β. The necessity
for capital market intervention to restore welfare maximum is indicated. Suppose the firm
accepts a fraction f of qI. Then, the firm will choose
Kg = θY/fq(r + δ)
This will be equal to Kw if
f = (1 – 1/η) Y–1/η = (1 – 1/η)p
Clearly, as η increases, the firm can be made to bear a greater share of the cost without reducing
welfare substantially. Lower values of η and difficulties in appropriability necessitate greater
equity financing of capital investments of the firm.
These results may now be generalized by including the firm’s investment in R&D. The
only essential modification is in the production function. For, it now depends on both types of
capital. Let
Y = RαKβ ; 0 ≤ α,β ≤ 1
The problem for the firm is now to choose K and R so as to

Max ∫ e–rt [RαKβ – E – qI] dt
0

subject to
dR/dt = E – εR
dK/dt = I – δK
It can be readily verified that the optimal choices are
R = αY/(r + ε), and
K = βY/(r + δ)
That is, the results developed earlier carry over. It should now be obvious that
• R chosen by a monopoly will be less than the welfare maximizing ideal if the
elasticity of demand is low
• it can be restored partially if an increase in R shifts the demand curve to the right
and enables the firm to appropriate the profit potential inherent in the market.
76 Economics of Biotechnology

• capital market intervention, in the form of partially financing R&D expenditures


may have the effect of restoring welfare maximum.
One further aspect of the demand for biotechnology products should be kept in perspective.
In the context of pharmaceutical products, in particular, the demand depends not only on the
private individual’s ability to pay for them but also on the nature of the national health schemes
and health insurance policies that they have. Similarly, if the physician does not prescribe a
specific brand drug the pharmacist may substitute a cheaper chemical-based product.
Agricultural biotechnology is also subject to similar changes in demand due to consumer
preferences for traditional varieties over GM products. The qualitative nature of the above
analysis is still valid though the quantitative choices of R&D expenditures change as a result
of these policies.

4.9 FINANCING CONSTRAINTS


Early stages of biotechnology development involve large investments with no marketable
output for a considerable time. Even at later stages, when the products enter regulatory approval
phase the uncertainties are rather large. The scientist discoverers and/or the NBFs do not
have their own resources for the necessary investments. Consequently, there are financing
problems associated with the
• sources of finance
• cost of capital
• organizational and motivational problems associated with the method of finance
chosen by the entrepreneur
Consider the following simple examples to appreciate the role of uncertainty on the cost of
capital. Let a venture capital firm provide capital v to a NBF. Suppose the risk free market rate of
interest is r. Then, the venture capitalist expects to recover v(1 + r). However, when the amount
v is invested in a biotechnology firm the probability of success is p; 0 ≤ p ≤ 1. If he charges an
interest rate rv the expected recovery is pv(1+rv). Hence, the likely choice of rv is such that
p(1 + rv) = 1 + r
That is, if r = 0.05, and p = 0.75, then rv = 0.2. In other words, the interest rate increases to 20
percent as opposed to a normal 5 percent. Private equity placements have a similar effect. The
analysis of the earlier sections therefore suggests that both R&D investments as well as those
on physical capital will be reduced ceteris paribus.
Note that, as Aghion and Tirole (1994) and several others noted, the uncertainty associated
with biotechnology projects also affects the market value of the assets of the firm and its revenue
generating ability.
The positive effect of sourcing finances from outside are
• limited liability of the NBF
• increased commitment of the NBF to make the venture succeed
Investment and Financing 77

• the venture capitalist and/or the large firm may also contribute its expertise and
control capabilities to ensure efficient performance (see, for example, Wolf and
Zilberman (1999)).
• Gerpacio (2003) pointed out that in the context of agricultural biotechnology
external financing from government sources is an essential complement of private
research on seeds. For, extension services, in the form of distribution systems,
grain harvest, post harvest facilities, and marketing are essential to achieve
success. Similarly, drug delivery through national health policies, and insurance
schemes define the success of pharmaceutical research.
• In addition, association with a large outside firm may signal higher value and
ability to attract additional finances as necessary. See, for instance, Lensink et al.
(2003).
On the downside it must be recognized that
• there may be a reduction in the level of motivation of the NBF and a reduction in
the returns from its effort
• the government, if it is the source of finance, may put limits on the type of activities
undertaken as well as control the prices of the products sold on the market. This
was noted in Kalaitzandonakes (1999).
• the venture capitalist and the large firms may emphasize marketability rather than
social welfare thereby restricting some applications that may have the potential to
augment social wellbeing
• outside investors experience information asymmetry with respect to the probability
of success of a venture and the expected market value of the innovation. This may
make them reluctant to finance some otherwise worthwhile investments. See, for
example, Ferreira and Brooks (2000) and Lerner et al. (2003)
• the outside financing agent will also generally claim property rights and royalties
from the revenue generated. Due to the limited bargaining power of the NBF the
larger firm or private financing agent may usurp disproportionate control rights.
See, Lerner et al. (2003).
The negative effect may be somewhat reduced in the case where large business houses
provide the finances. In particular, unlike short term financing by outside agents they provide
stable long term relationships. See, for example, Lensink et al. (2003). In general, private
placements can be arranged quickly. They also allow greater monitoring of the managers of
the NBF. However, all such finances may be available only at the margin and after public
sector institutions made substantial investments. Lerner et al. (2003) reported that when there
is a reduction in government financial support NBFs are more likely to seek alliances with
large firms rather than depend on the capital market. One of the reasons may well be that their
experiences reduce problems of information asymmetry. The other reason may be the possibility
of obtaining assistance in getting regulatory approvals, marketing products, and so on.
In sum, there are various factors that affect both the market value of R&D and its costs. As
of now it is difficult to model each of these effects in detail. However, the following approach
78 Economics of Biotechnology

illustrates their effects. Fundamentally, the returns to the NBF from cumulative R&D
represented by R can be written as sRα. There are forces that tend to reduce s as well as those
that contribute to an increase in s. Similarly, let i represent the generalized cost incurred by
the NBF in effectively integrating an expenditure E on R&D. The problem of the optimal choice
of E can therefore be represented as

Max ∫ e–rt [sRα – iE] dt
0
subject to
dR/dt = E – εR
The optimal R can therefore be written as
R = αsV/i(r + ε)
Clearly, the NBFs seek finances from outside sources to the extent that they can augment the
market value of their assets in excess of the costs of obtaining finances and loss of control.
However, as of now, it is difficult to precisely specify the extent to which external financing
would be beneficial to a NBF.

4.10 FURTHER CONSIDERATIONS


It was noted, in chapter 2, that network organizational structures are prominent in the
biotechnology industry. When a large chemical or seed firm finances a part of the R&D
expenditure of a NBF it will expect to receive a share of the value generated. Intuitively, the
share of the large firm will contain a risk premium in addition to the share of finances that it
provides. However, it has been difficult to extend the models of section 4.2 to accommodate
this aspect.
Refer to Section 4.8. The value of the firm, given K and R, depends on both. However, the
formulation of the model, of the optimal choices of K and R, is that the user cost of capital of
either of these investments depends only on δ or ε. It would be more plausible to expect both
δ and ε to affect the cost of capital of R and K. Further modifications of the framework are
indicated.
Financing constraints, coupled with the risks of biotechnology R&D investments, can be
generally expected to influence the expenditure on R&D. However, it has been rather difficult
to articulate formal models. Models, dealing with capital market imperfections on the choice
of K alone, do not provide adequate guidelines.
Recall, from chapter 2, that the principal–agent model provides a useful approach to
network relationships. It can therefore be argued that the choice of R and K must be articulated
from a similar perspective. However, such dynamic generalizations are not available so far.
On the whole, several questions have yet to be addressed though some useful results
about R&D investments are available.
Demand, Cost, and Productivity 79

Chapter 5

DEMAND, COST, AND PRODUCTIVITY

5.1 THE BACKGROUND


The foregoing chapter considered the environment in which R&D and capital investment
activity takes place in the context of biotechnology. Irrespective of the locus of these investments,
viz., private firms or public sector institutions, the ultimate purpose of biotechnology is to
improve the wellbeing of the consumers and the firms that manufacture the products. To that
extent it is necessary to understand something about the demand for such products.
Consider the case of pharmaceutical products. In any given therapeutic class, directed
towards a specific disease, there are substitutable products. Some of them may be based on
biotechnology, others on chemical based technologies, and so on. In a few cases, where the
consumer directly pays for them, he may reveal his preferences. However, in most of the
situations encountered in practice, it is the physician or the pharmacist who make the choice
on the basis of their assessment of the patients’ ability to pay, their experience with the drug,
and so on. It is also possible to argue that the ability to pay may be conditioned by the insurance
policy of the patient and/or national policies of public health. Demand theory has not been
able to come to grips with all these complexities. Instead, most of the literature considers the
problem in a conventional manner. The main emphasis is on the effect of substitutable products
within a given therapeutic class. The context of the demand for diagnostic kits is much less
clear. For, it is essentially the judgement of the physician that determines their use in the case
of any one patient. A battery of tests and drugs may go together while determining efficient
treatment. Given this scenario there is no significant resistance to the use of biotechnology
drugs. Some ethical issues regarding stem cell transplants and so on have been raised but they
do not probably have any significant effect on the demand for pharmaceutical products.
There are three types of issues with respect to agricultural biotechnology. Firstly, instances
can be found where genetically modified foods and non-GM foods are accepted by consumers
80 Economics of Biotechnology

without any distinction. Soybean usage in the U.S.A. seems to be of this kind. Secondly, in the
context of milk products the animals may be treated with rBST (recombinant bovine
somatotropin) but the milk itself is free from any genetically modified material. Even so,
consumers have been demanding that these products be appropriately labeled and their
preference for non-genetically modified varieties honored. The sensitivity is much greater in
the context of food crops like soybeans (especially in the European Union (EU)), rice, wheat,
and others. Thirdly, there is only a derived demand for genetically modified seeds like Bt
cotton. The economic factors, that determine such derived demand, are different from those
alluded to in conventional demand theory.
In sum, understanding the demand for biotechnology products requires different sets of
tools depending on the context. It is not possible to detail all the idiosyncracies. A few major
aspects will be examined.
The success of biotechnology depends on a variety of other factors as well. In the context
of agricultural biotechnology the most important aspects are the
• complementary input use, such as pesticides, fertilizer etc.
• price of genetically modified seed
• increase in output achieved by pesticide resistance and herbicide tolerance
• increases in prices achieved (may be purely due to the monopoly power of the firm
rather than superior quality and consequent consumer willingness to pay)
In particular, the profit of a firm can be represented by
π = pyY – TC
where
π = total profit
py = price per unit of Y
Y = total output, and
TC = total cost of producing and marketing Y
In turn, TC can be written as
TC = pS S + pPP
where
ps = price per unit of S
S = quantity of seeds used
pp = price per unit of pesticides
P = volume of pesticide use
Bt varieties of seeds reduce the use of pesticide. However, there will be significant changes
in the use of complementary inputs like irrigation, fertilizer, and so on. Cost reduction is not
assured unless something is known about the use of other factors of production. It is therefore
Demand, Cost, and Productivity 81

necessary to investigate the


• use of inputs on a given farm
• the price of Bt seeds
• total cost per hectare of cultivation
• changes in output achieved through the use of GM varieties
These factors determine total cost.
Improvement in the production conditions and/or an increase in productivity may still
not result in profitability for the firm adopting biotechnology. It depends on the consumer
acceptance of biotechnology products and their willingness to pay and/or the monopoly power
of the firm.
With these dimensions of the use of biotechnology in perspective this chapter analyzes
• demand for the products of the firm
• productivity of biotechnology
• costs of production
• profitability of new products
• distribution of gains between consumers and firms
However, the effects of biotechnology on the structure of markets and price determination
will be the emphasis of the next chapter. For, they present conceptually different issues for
economic analysis.

5.2 PATTERNS OF DEMAND


As noted above, one of the important links is the evaluation of the consumer’s willingness
to pay. This is generally stated in the form of the demand curve.
Consider the demand for pharmaceutical products. Assume that the consumer is choosing
a non-GM (based on traditional chemical technology) versus a GM product. Both are available
on the market and the products are indistinguishable so long as they are not specifically labeled.
Under these conditions the total amount of output bought, viz.,
X = Xn + Xg
where
Xn = amount of non-GM drugs bought, and
Xg = amount of the GM drugs bought
is the only variable entering the utility (gross value) function of the consumer. The utility
function can be stated as
U = aXε + Y ; a > 0
where
Y = any other commodity in the consumer budget or simply
the expenditure on all other goods (assuming py = 1).
82 Economics of Biotechnology

The consumer chooses X and Y so as to maximize U subject to the income constraint


pxX + Y = I
where
p = price per unit of X
Note that p is the same for both Xn and Xg because they are indistinguishable. The demand for
X will then be
X = Ap–η
where
η = 1/(1–ε), and
A = (aε)η
It is generally noted that even within the category of GM drugs there are substitutable
varieties in the same therapeutic class. Added to this is the option of traditional chemical
technology based drugs. Though they are substitutable in general, their prices are kept distinct
in the market. This is surely one dimension along which competition manifests itself.
When Xn and Xg are indistinguishable they can be considered as perfectly substitutable.
Hence, the utility function can be represented by
U = XgαXnβ
It can be readily verified that the demand for GM drugs will now be
Xg = α(I – Y)/(α + β)pg
so that the elasticity of demand is unity. However, in practice, this is unrealistic.
Another way of representing the substitutability, following Fink (2000), is to write
X = (wnXnρ + wgXgρ)1/ρ ; wn + wg = 1
where w’s are the distribution parameters that represent the relative importance of the two
types of preparations and ρ is a parameter reflecting the extent of substitution. It is well known
that the elasticity of substitution between them is
σ = 1/ (1 – ρ)
That is, Xn and Xg are not perfectly substitutable. The gross value now becomes
U = a (wnXnρ + wgXgρ)ε/ρ + Y
The consumer maximizes U subject to the budget constraint
pnXn + pgXg + Y = I
where
pn = price per unit of Xn, and
pg = price per unit of Xg
Explicit optimization results in
Xg = E wn–σ (pg/p)-σ
Demand, Cost, and Productivity 83

where the composite price index p is given by


p = [wn–ρpg1–ρ + wg–ρpn1–ρ]–1/ρ, and
E = I–Y
In some recent literature there is a suggestion that non-GM varieties may be preferred so long
as their supply lasts. In other words, GM varieties can be sold only when the non-GM supplies
are exhausted. This subtlety can be incorporated in the above framework by placing suitable
limits on the value of the parameter a.
However, pharmaceutical products are generally not labeled and the consumer (or his
physician who writes the prescription) does not discriminate between them except for the
utility they offer and the purchasing power of the patient. Imperfect substitutability will
primarily be a result of cumulative experiences with a specific drug. However, their prices
may remain distinct thereby suggesting that the above analysis is more meaningful in practice.
The above formulation is generally valid even in the context of agricultural biotechnology
so long as the GM and non-GM varieties coexist. However, the analytical requirements are
somewhat different if the products are labeled.
One of the major modifications, as suggested by Giannakis and Fulton (2000) and Fulton
and Giannakis (2004), concerns the fact that the firms do not apriori know the relative
preferences of a consumer for non-GM versus GM varieties. Further, the specification must be
consistent with the stylized fact; viz., that consumers prefer non-GM products when both are
offered at the same price. Hence, the following assumptions are pertinent.
• Each consumer purchases 1 unit of the commodity in whatever form they choose.
• c represents the distinguishing characteristic of a consumer relating to the choice
between non-GM and GM varieties.
• αc represents the consumer’s aversion to GM products. That is, consumers with
large c are more likely to prefer the non-GM products.
• Assume that c varies randomly over (0, C) and postulate a uniform distribution.
A typical consumer has three options on which he can spend his income; the non-GM
variety, the GM variety, or some other commodity (viz., the Y in the above model). To simplify
comparisons measure the quantities of these purchases in such a way that they yield the same
gross value U per unit of consumption. The net values are then represented by
Un = U – pn for the non-GM variety
Ug = U – pg – αc for the GM variety, and
Us = U –1 for the substitutable variety
The price per unit of the substitutable product is parameterized as unity as in the previous
modeling exercise.
A consumer is indifferent between a GM and non-GM variety provided Ug = Un. That is,
U – pn = U – pg – αc

84 Economics of Biotechnology

Hence, the corresponding value of c is


c = (pn – pg)/α
All the consumers, with a value of c less than or equal to this, will prefer the GM product.
Hence,
Xg = quantity of the GM product demanded
= (pn – pg)/α
Note that in this formulation pg ≤ pn invariably. The empirical validity of this implication can
be contested if the unit cost of producing the GM variety is higher.
Consider the possibility that the consumer prefers the substitutable product over the GM
variety. This will occur whenever
U – 1 ≥ U – pg – αc
or, equivalently,
c ≥ (1 – pg)/α
Assume, for purposes of argument, that pn > 1. Then, it is obvious that
Y = (1 – pg)/ α
and, consequently,
X n = C – Xg – Y
The above argument assumed that the non-GM and GM foods are labeled and sold at different
prices. Consider the situation where there is no such labeling. Then, pg = pn since they are not
distinguishable. Let θ represent the probability of an actual purchase being a GM variety. Assuming
that the consumer can recognize it ex post (i.e., when he consumes it) the expected utility will be
Ue = θ(U – p – αc) + (1 – θ) (U – p)
= U – p – θαc
X will be preferred over Y if and only if
U – p – θαc > U – 1
That is,
1 – p > θαc
Hence, the demand for X becomes
X = (1 – p)/θα
The above formulation assumed that the consumer derives the same gross value from the
consumption of a unit of GM and non-GM products. Differences in valuation can be built into
the framework in the following manner. Rewrite the net value as
Ug = θg – pg
U n = θ n – pn
with the possibility that θg > θn. The consumer will then buy GM products if and only if
Demand, Cost, and Productivity 85

θg > pg + (θn – pn)


The demand for GM products will then be
Xg = C – (pg + θn – pn)
It may be expected that pg > pn though θg/pg > θn/pn. To an extent this scaling was implied in
the earlier formulation.
Neither of these approaches contains any reasons for the preference of non-GM over GM
products. They only allow a derivation of the demand curves if such a distinction exists.
One further observation is in order. Most biotechnology based products are produced in
networked organizations. Similarly, most of these products are supported by strong patent
rights. In either case, the firms derive a degree of monopoly power that has not been taken
into account in obtaining the demand curves so far. There is no definite analytical argument to
fall back upon. The following approach is indicative of the general direction.
Assume that there are Xg number of consumers of GM products with each one purchasing
one unit of output. As Xg increases the marginal valuation of the commodity decreases. Let
pg = α – aXg
where
α = maximum price consumers are willing to pay, and
Xg = number of units of output bought
It can be expected that only Xg/ψ individuals will pay if property rights are not strict. The
rest will use pirated versions. That is, when property rights are not perfect and costless to
enforce the patent holder may not be in a position to exclude all pirating or he may find it
costly to do so. Such weakly enforced property rights would result in payments from a fraction
ψ of customers only. The marginal valuation will therefore become
pg = α – aXg/ψ
This is one approach suggested in the literature. A second version suggests that pirating
will occur only when pg is high. Consequently, in the presence of weak property rights, there
is a fraction φ of value such that any price above that leads to piracy. There is a limit to monopoly
exploitation of IPRs. Hence, the effective demand curve can be represented by
pg = φ(α – aXg) ; φ < 1
It may be concluded that some issues related to the demand for GM versus non-GM foods
have not been resolved.

5.3 PRODUCTIVITY
When products of biotechnology and conventionally produced output coexist in the market
the market penetration of biotechnology products depends on advantages either in terms of
the quality of products, lower prices, and/or advantages in the cost of production. Monopoly
prices of biotechnology products, that are a result of patents and IPR protection, are unlikely
86 Economics of Biotechnology

to be lower. In the case of corn the higher oil content has been value enhancing. In general,
however, there is no overwhelming quality improvement in the use of products of
biotechnology. This makes the study of productivity and costs and their contribution to
profitability important.
The simplest analytical argument would be that the productivity of biotechnology seeds
(Bt cotton or roundup ready soybeans) and other such inputs like rBST save the farmers from
utilization of certain resources and thereby increase productivity. In other words, partial
productivity measures like
Y/S = output/quantity of seed used
= average productivity of seeds, and
∂Y/∂S = marginal productivity of seeds
convey adequate information about productivity improvements.
One difficulty with this approach is that the prices of biotechnology seeds and inputs like
rBST are more expensive relative to the conventional factors of production. That is, the
advantages due to increases in partial productivity measures may be more than neutralized
by such price increases. It is necessary to conceptualize a productivity measure that accounts
for this. Suppose pn is the price per unit of non-GM seed whereas pg is the price of GM seeds.
Then, pgSg/pn can be viewed as the equivalent non-GM seed use when Sg units of GM seeds
are utilized. The partial productivity measure may be modified as
pnY/pgSg = average productivity of conventional seed equivalent.
Clearly, whenever pg > pn, the expected productivity increases will have to be discounted.
A more serious difficulty with partial productivity measures is that they do not adequately
account for cost reductions of substitutable inputs. For instance, by their nature Bt and RR
varieties of seeds economize on the use of pesticides or herbicides as the case may be. However,
some inputs, such as fertilizers and irrigation, may be complementary in that GM varieties
need more of these resources to achieve the expected output increases. In essence, S, in itself,
cannot explain all the output increase achieved by using GM seeds. Other factors contribute to
the output increases significantly. Basically, therefore, a total productivity measure is necessary
to appreciate the advantages derived from biotechnology.
To keep the presentation simple assume that the production process utilizes only two inputs,
seeds (S) and pesticides (P). Let ps and pp denote the respective prices per unit. The pesticides
used in both GM and non-GM production are the same. Hence, pp does not change whatever
type of crop is cultivated. However, ps may be different. It is therefore convenient to convert all
types of inputs into units of P. In particular, the use of seeds is equivalent to psS/pp equivalent
units of pesticide use. Hence, the total input use for either technology can be written as
TFU = total factor use
= psS/pp + P
Demand, Cost, and Productivity 87

The total factor productivity can now be defined by


TFP = Y/TFU
= PpY/(psS + ppP)
It is important to acknowledge one other possibility. When GM technology displaces non-
GM technology it is possible that the number of inputs will also change. For instance, a certain
periphery of the farm may be mandated to use non-GM varieties for ecological and
environmental reasons. Similarly, the nature of harvesting GM crops change as the Bt varieties
yield larger outputs. The approach to total productivity suggested here can accommodate
such changes as well.
One implication of this approach is important. Suppose the total productivity of GM
varieties is higher. This may be a result of
• a reduction in ps/pp
• a reduction in S
• a reduction in P
• an increase in Y per hectare
• a reduction in pp obtained in the short run due to the reduction in the demand for P
The following numerical example may be helpful in appreciating the issues at stake in
greater detail. Consider the production of non-GM varieties first. Assume that the production
process requires seeds (S), pesticides (P), fertilizer (F), and labor (L). Let one unit of output (Y)
be produced and sold at a price 1 per unit. Assume that the
cost of seeds = 0.2
cost of pesticides = 0.15
cost of fertilizer = 0.15
cost of labor = 0.3
Then, the productivity = 1/0.8 = 1.25
Contrast this with the production of a GM variety. Let the prices of these seeds be 1.3 (or, 30%
more than non-GM). The
cost of seeds = 0.26
Let the other costs change as follows.
cost of pesticide = 0.075 (50% reduction in cost for Bt varieties)
cost of fertilizer = 0.18 (20% increase)
cost of labor = 0.36 (20% increase because output increases)
Y = output from the same quantity of seed = 1.2
Suppose the price per unit of Y is the same. Then the revenue is 1.2 and the cost is 0.875.
Hence, the productivity is 1.43. GM varieties are then superior.
88 Economics of Biotechnology

However, suppose for the sake of argument that seed costs double. Then the productivity
is 1.2/1.075; i.e., it decreases. Assume, instead, that the costs of fertilizer and irrigation increase
by 50%. The productivity decreases.
In other words, the entire choice of inputs changes when moving from a non-GM to a GM
variety. An appropriate mix of input may be necessary to maintain an increase in output. This
may not, however, result in an increase in productivity.
These aspects have been examined empirically in the context of several biotechnologies.
Some representative examples will now be considered.
(a) Consider the case of rBST. This is a genetically engineered hormone injected into
cows to increase milk yield. The technology is simple, does not require heavy fixed
investments, and has minimal start-up costs. However, it was reported that comple-
mentary inputs and certain management practices are necessary to obtain a higher
yield of milk. In particular, the farm should invest in total mixed ration (TMR) that
improves the quality of feed mix supplied to cows. This investment is large and
can be justified only when the herd size is sufficiently large. It was reported that
the increase in the costs of complementary inputs generally reduces total factor
productivity. In other words, the increases in milk yields, if any, have not been
commensurate with associated costs. The increases in the quality of milk in the form
of increased shelf life have been inconsequential. It was also pointed out that
increased yields may occur only with younger herds. Biotechnology cannot be a
miracle to increase productivity if the cows are already barren or their productivity
is low. These results were recorded in Foltz and Chang (2002) and Barham et al.
(2004).
(b) The use of porcene somatotropin (PST) appears to have a different impact. PST is
produced in the pituitary of pigs. It is a naturally produced protein. Supplemental
PST produced through genetic modification was reported to have affected feed
efficiency, average daily weight gain, and production of leaner meat. TFP increased
in general. See, for instance, Lemieux and Wohlgenant (1989).
(c) Bt cotton is widely cultivated and its productivity extensively studied. The follow-
ing observations are salient.
• A major problem with growing cotton is the crop damage due to insects and pests;
especially the bollworms. The damages caused by bollworms are more important
in the early phases of the crop cycle and hence have a significant impact on plant
development and crop yield. See, for instance, Klotz-Ingram et al. (1999), Qaim
(2003), and Bennet et al. (2004).
• Cotton production requires herbicides to control weeds. Two or more herbicides
are necessary at planting stage. Post-emergent (i.e., after the weeds are noticed)
herbicides will be needed at later stages in the production cycle. This was noted
in Klotz-Ingram et al. (1999).
• Bt varieties of cotton contain in-built resistance to pests. It was reported in Qaim
(2003) and Bennet et al. (2004) that the use of insecticide can be reduced to about
Demand, Cost, and Productivity 89

one third of the conventional varieties. That is, even Bt adopters had to use some
bollworm insecticide. For, as Bennet et al. (2004) remarked, the resistance to pests
that is characteristic of the Bt varieties, diminished with the age of the plant. The
advantage of Bt varieties is not only in the quantitative reduction in pesticide use
but also in the number of sprayings thereby reducing other variable costs as well.
See Qaim (2003) and Traxler (2004). Koltz-Ingram et al. (1999) pointed out that Bt
cotton growers may discontinue the use of BT foliar sprays and pyrethoids.
• There is no difference in the use of pesticides against sucking pests.
• Morse et al. (2005) reported that Bt varieties save on irrigation costs while they use
a great deal more of inorganic chemical fertilizers.
• Costs of harvesting Bt varieties are reported to be higher since the yield is higher.
Refer to Qaim (2003).
• Bt seeds costs are higher than traditional seed. Farmers also generally pay technol-
ogy fees to cover the fixed costs of R&D. See, for example, Koltz-Ingram (1999) and
Qaim (2003).
• The increases in the yield per hectare are critically dependent on the soil, nutrient
application, pest pressure and a variety of other factors. This was noted in Huang
et al. (2003).
When all these factors are taken into account it was generally concluded that there is no
significant gain in the total factor productivity as a result of the use of biotechnology. Fulton
and Keyowski (1999) reported similar results for herbicide tolerant canola.

5.4 VARIABLE COSTS


The second building block to determine the welfare gains from biotechnology is the cost
of production and supply behavior of firms. It has been acknowledged that the fixed costs of
conducting the research, the share of this cost that the private firms need to absorb, and the
intellectual property rights accorded to private investors have a decisive role.
The definition of TFP utilized in the previous section suggests that the average cost of
production can be written as
AC = pp/TFP
In the short run, to the extent that the adoption of Bt varieties reduces the use of pesticides,
pp will be reduced. Hence, the reduction in AC will depend on the reduction in pp if TFP is
declining simultaneously. Both Qaim (2003) and Morse et al. (2005) concluded that Bt varieties
do not generally reduce the average cost primarily due to high costs of Bt seeds.
However, this section will only consider the variable costs of delivering output from
technologies whose operational feasibility is already established.
There is a universal acknowledgement that the yield on farm lands, for the application of
the same seed variety and pesticide/herbicide combination recommended by the seed
company, tends to be very different. This depends on the agro climatic conditions, the initial
90 Economics of Biotechnology

incidence of insects and weeds and so on. Analysis of variable costs should keep this in
perspective.
It is generally suggested that the GM varieties of crops increase the productivity of farm
lands. For example, the crop season for Bt cotton can be extended thereby increasing the yield.
Similar is the case of yield increases if pest elimination and herbicide tolerance can be achieved.
However, note that pest control inputs differ fundamentally from other inputs. For, though
potential output from given seeds cannot be altered, increases in yield are a result of pest
control or herbicide tolerance. That is, only the fraction of potential output recovered depends
on pesticide or herbicide usage. Refer to Lichtenberg and Zilberman (1986). This is reflected
by writing the production function as
Y = actual crop yield
= f (X) G(Z)
where
X = vector of inputs like seeds and fertilizer, and
Z = quantities of pesticide or herbicide
In practice, the upper limit on G(Z) is unity. Hence, the logistic specification
G(Z) = [1 + exp(a – bI – cBt)]–1
where
I = amount of insecticide sprayed on the farm, and
Bt = amount of insect resistance expected from the Bt variety
of seeds was considered satisfactory.
See, for example, Qaim (2003).
The following alternative is sometimes conceptualized. Notice that the seed company, that
sells the GM seeds, specifies fixed quantities of seed and pesticide use per hectare. This may
indicate a possible reduction in the average cost of producing the crop if the use of GM seeds
reduces the use of pesticides while increasing the price of seed. However, depending on the
nature of the farm, the benefits may vary. Technically there may be perfect substitution
between the pest control offered by the Bt seeds and the external use of pesticides. However,
the efficiency with which they eliminate pests may vary. This is usually reflected by a Cobb-
Douglas production function
Y = XαZβ ; 0 ≤ α, β ≤ 1
The values of α and β in this specification are the efficiency parameters. However, note that
the substitution between X and Z is not a result of the variations in the prices of X and Z.
Hence, the derivation of a conventional cost function from this will be inadequate.
The following approach will be more direct. The cost of producing Y is
C(Y) = pgX + qZ
Demand, Cost, and Productivity 91

where
pg = price per unit of GM seeds, and
q = price per unit of the insecticide
The average cost of production is
AC = C(Y)/Y
In general, it was noted that C(Y) associated with GM varieties exceeds those of non-GM
crops. Hence, even if GM crops decrease average costs for the agro climatic conditions for
which they were designed, they may not be effective if the incidence of insects is higher.
The third aspect that received attention is the possibility that the output of the GM varieties
is qualitatively superior. For example, genetically modified corn contains more oil. The
production and cost function specifications can address this issue by an appropriate choice of
output measure. In the context of the above example the amount of oil extracted is a better
measure compared to the quantity of corn produced.
The above approaches estimate the average cost of GM and non-GM crops separately.
However, it can be expected that the actual choices of the farmer depend on profit maximization.
It would be useful to investigate the comparison of average costs in such a framework. The
following approach, adapted from Lamarie and Marette (2002), and Zilberman et al. (2004) is
illustrative. Assume that the nature of the farm can be characterized by its pest infestation or
the incidence of weeds. Suppose that, as a result of this, the farmer can get only a fraction θ of
the potential output from the farm. Let θ be a random variable distributed uniformly over
(0,1). Consider a non-GM variety of crop being planted on the farm. Denote by xn the quantity
of seed and pesticide combination required per hectare. Suppose the potential output from
the farm is yn. Then, the profit from the farm is
πn = pθyn – qnxn
where
p = market price of a unit of yn , and
qn = price per unit of xn
A farmer will use these seeds if and only if πn ≥ 0. That is,
θn ≥ qnxn/pyn
The average cost of production on this farm will be
ACn = qnxn/θyn for θ ≤ θn
Hence, the maximum average cost for the non-GM crop is
ACnm = p when θ = θn
Now, suppose that Bt varieties or Roundup Ready varieties of seeds are available. When
these crops are planted the profit becomes
πg = pθyg –qgxg
92 Economics of Biotechnology

The assumption here is that the GM and non-GM crops are indistinguishable and there is no
labeling. This formulation captures the benefits of GM varieties through yg only. A suitable
modification is needed if θ decreases over the long run. Clearly, a farmer, considering the GM
variety in isolation, will adopt it if and only if
θ ≤ qgxg/pyg
The minimum AC is again
ACgm = p at θ = θg
Consider the possibility that θg < θn.. Clearly, this happens if the costs of using GM varieties
are lower and/or the yields are higher. GM varieties will be always preferred over non-GM
varieties if this occurs. However, the case where θn < θg is more appropriate in empirically
observed contexts. For, as of now, both non-GM and GM varieties coexist in practice. Clearly,
ACn < ACg at θ = θg. Under these conditions the farmer will prefer the GM varieties over the
non-GM crops whenever
pθyg – qgxg > pθyn –qnxn
That is,
pθδyg > δcg
where
δyg = yg – yn, and δcg = qgxg – qnxn
Hence, the relevant range of θ is
θg1 ≥ δcg/pδyg
The only relevant case for analysis is where θg1 > θg. For, otherwise the farmer will not use the
GM varieties. A comparison of ACg1 with ACg now suggests that ACg > ACn at θ = θg implies
that ACg1 > ACn for all θg1 ≥ θg. It is always more expensive to use the GM seeds.
However, in practice, several studies, such as Klotz-Ingram et al. (1999) and Qaim (2003)
suggest that ACg < ACn. Two possibilities have been recorded. First, the costs may be reduced.
For, production of non-herbicide tolerant crops typically requires two chemical applications:
one pre-emergent and the other post-emergent. The post-emergent application controls only
a limited spectrum of weeds. In the context of herbicide tolerant crops the chemical is applied
only once. This improves the yield by removing competition with herbs for moisture and
nutrients. It also eliminates the cost of additional machine operations over the field. Second,
though the cost per hectare (seed + pesticide) increases, the yield increases substantially so as
to make AC lower. This may however be observed only on farms where the initial incidence
of pests is low. Huygen et al. (2004) observed that average costs are higher if labeling costs are
included.
In sum, it is not possible to establish the average cost reduction achieved by planting GM
seeds either theoretically or empirically. It may occur only in some cases where the initial pest
incidence is low.
Demand, Cost, and Productivity 93

The adoption of Bt varieties depend on profitability even when the average costs are rising.
For,
π = [pyY/TC –1]TC
where
π = total profit
py = price per unit of Y
TC = total cost of producing and marketing Y
The profitability for the firm adopting biotechnology also depends on consumer acceptance
of such products and their willingness to pay and/or monopoly power of the firm.
Both in the context of rBST milk and Bt cotton it was generally reported that the profitability
and profits did not increase. See, Barham et al. (2003), Huang et al. (2003), Bennet et al. (2004),
and Caswell et al. (1998).

5.5 WELFARE EFFECTS


Recall, from section 5.2, that the demand curves for GM and non-GM products can be
expressed in the form
Xg = (pn – pg)/α, and
Xn = C – (pn – pg)/α
Explicitly plotting the net utility from the two varieties, as in Fig. 1, it can be inferred that
U

B
Un Un

Ug
O
C* c
Fig. 1
the GM varieties are preferable from the consumer viewpoint so long as c < c* = (pn – pg)/α.
Hence, it follows that the increase in consumer surplus as a result of the introduction of the
GM crops is the area ABUn. Algebraically it is given by
CS = (pn – pg)2/ 2α
In the above analysis it was assumed that the two products have been labeled explicitly
and sold at different prices. To consider the case where they are indistinguishable recall from
94 Economics of Biotechnology

section 5.2 that the demand for X = Xn + Xg becomes


X = (1 – p)/θα
where θ is the fraction of the GM crop that is sold on the market. The net consumer benefit will
then be
CS = (1 – p)2/2θα
Labeling will improve consumer welfare if and only if
(pn – pg)2θ > (1 – p)2
That is, labeling will be beneficial whenever the products can be distinguished sharply and
priced accordingly and/or there is a greater fraction of GM crop on the market. Giannakis and
Fulton (2002) presented such a comparison of welfare effects.
Fulton and Keyowski (1999) made an attempt to capture the benefits to the producer in
the following manner. Suppose the firms differ with respect to some characteristic like the
incidence of pests or the abilities of the farmer. Assume that this characteristic f is uniformly
distributed over (0,F). Represent the profit from the GM and non-GM crops by
πg = pgyg – qgxg + γf, and
πn = pnyn – qnxn + βf
The notations here are the same as in section 5.3. Since the GM seeds better resist pests it can
be expected that γ > β. Notice that GM crops will be utilized on the farm whenever
f ≥ ∆/(γ – β)
where
∆ = (pnyn – pgyg) – (qnxn – qgxg)
It can be therefore inferred that
Xn = supply of non-GM output
= ∆/(γ – β), and
Xg = F – ∆/(γ – β)
Clearly, both are increasing functions of the respective prices. The net increase in profit is
given by the area CBB* in Fig. 2.

Fig. 2
96 Economics of Biotechnology

Xdn = demand for non-GM products


= C – (pn – pg)/α, and
= supply of non-GM varieties
= ∆/ (γ – β)
Hence, the market determines pn by equilibrating supply and demand. The net welfare is the
area between the demand and supply curves upto the point of equilibrium.
A similar analysis holds for GM crops. Extensions, to determine qg and qn, , can also be
conceptualized.
In practice, the GM crops are produced under patent protection. Hence, the seed producers
and/or the farmers will determine qg and pg. Such extensions of the analysis are also straight
forward.
Market segmentation, achieved through labeling, may enable the producers of GM varieties
to extract some consumer surplus thereby making their production more profitable. Even
these analytical details of Lence and Hayes (2003), Anderson et al. (2004), and Noussair et al.
(2004) can be developed in an analogous manner.

5.6 SUMMING UP
The present chapter highlighted some essential features of biotechnology. It also made an
attempt to examine how economics can explain the emergence of these features and the
consequences for pricing, investment, and economic welfare.
The empirically observed patterns are rather diverse. They vary with the particular
biotechnology under consideration as well as the nature of the emerging market structure for
specific products. As such it is difficult to visualize one all encompassing analytical framework.
The variety of conflicting inferences from different models may be desirable but more attention
will be necessary to examine the sources of these differences.
Frisvold et al. (2003) noted that R&D investments create dynamic gains and not just one
time advantages. Hence, all the static productivity, profit analyses reported above are
inadequate.
Lence and Hays (2003) observed that it is possible that initially productivity and profits
are nil or negative. However, dynamically the market picks up with increased acceptance of
GM foods. Hence, a static analysis is inadequate.
Moon and Balasubramanian (2001) pointed that the core of the controversy over
biotechnology foods is the extent to which consumers perceive benefits from agricultural
biotechnology relative to its risks. The role of benefit perceptions in shaping willingness-to-
pay premium for non-GM was evaluated. Overall, risk perception exerted a stronger influence
on the willingness-to-pay for non-GM foods than did benefit perceptions.
In general, as Caswell et al. (1998) noted, the economic impact of biotechnology is likely to
be incremental and not dramatic as claimed by its proponents.
Market Structure and Pricing 97

Chapter 6

MARKET STRUCTURE AND PRICING

6.1 NATURE OF MARKETS


Theories of industrial organization generally acknowledge markets for products that are
directly sold to the consumers. For, the ultimate value of production depends on their
satisfaction. What the firm can recover out of the value to the consumer determines cost
recovery and profits to the firm. In the context of biotechnology the two major markets for
their products are pharmaceutical and agricultural products (mainly crops but they may also
include animal products). As yet, there are a few such final products in the biotechnology
industry. It may, as a result, be important to consider markets for some intermediate products
as well.
Gamberdella et al. (2000) consider four sets of variables as relevant sources of
competitiveness.
• Size and structure of biomedical education and research
• Basic institutions governing labor markets, skilled researchers, and managers
• Intellectual property rights and patent laws
• Nature and intensity of competition in the final product market
It may turn out that within the pharmaceutical group the market for diagnostic kits will
be different from that of prescription drugs. This happens due to two reasons. First, the
technical complexity and the costs of production are far less in the context of diagnostics.
Consequently, entry and exit are easier and a large number of firms may be expected in this
market. Second, patients do not directly buy the diagnostic kits. Instead, it is the physicians
who determine what need to be bought and used. Though they are expected to take the
income of the patient into account in their choices it need not always be the case. The markets
will surely change as the health insurance coverage increases. Even in a specific therapeutic
98 Economics of Biotechnology

class market demand depends on the combination of drugs that a physician prescribes and
whether or not he chooses the combination produced by the same firm. In the context of
biotechnology drugs it was noted that a firm may not have any particular advantage in
producing a second drug merely because it was successful in the first. That is, quite independent
of the physician’s propensities, the market structure depends on the production and marketing
competencies of the firm and its costs. The market for each drug may have its own dynamics
if the economies of scope are not significant.
Two other aspects have been highlighted. First, within each therapeutic class there may
be competing products based on biotechnology. The economies of scope and the nature of
patent rights may determine the number of products of each firm and the number of firms
in the market. Second, many drugs are such that substitutable products are currently produced
through the use of chemical technology. Products of biotechnology may not be distinct and
exclusive. There is also no assurance that such drugs will be cheaper. At least in the early
stages of drug development, where the scaling up of laboratory technology is still in progress,
the chemical firms may have an advantage. The market for drugs of a given therapeutic class
may therefore consist of both chemical and biotechnology firms.
Any one firm may find it advantageous to segment the market for its products based
on the mechanism of drug delivery. For instance, they may consider the bulk market through
the public health system as distinct from private prescription sales.
Large chemical firms are finding it increasingly advantageous for them to integrate into
the biotechnology markets. Initially this may be the result of their competence in clinical tests
and their ability to take a product through the regulatory process. The mergers and acquisitions
may also eventually give them the scientific and technical competence that they may find
expensive to develop in-house.
Defining the nature of the market becomes complex if a network of firms, including NBFs
and large chemical firms, produce a drug. For, even if the chemical firm has competitors for
its product it has distinct dynamic advantages if it is highly connected to NBFs. However,
the relationships between them are not arms length contracts. Instead, they are incomplete
contracts of a long duration. In general, biotechnology firms in the pharmaceutical industry
exhibit various degrees of vertical integration and contractual relationships. It is difficult to
apriori claim that all links of the vertical chain belong to the same industry. Fundamentally,
therefore, the degree of concentration in any therapeutic segment depends on a variety of
factors.
Gamberdilla et al. (2000) claim that concentration in the biotechnology industry is low
because
• the industry is composed of many therapeutic classes and a wide range of tech-
nologies
• the successful introduction of a new drug within a class and its advantages do not
last long. A major innovation is followed by product and process innovations by
competitors
Market Structure and Pricing 99

• an early innovator does not have any major advantage in introducing major drugs
later
Consider the markets for agricultural biotechnology. There are three distinct segments
here: seeds, crops, and animal products. Biopesticides and biofertilizers may also be sold
independently and not necessarily embodied in seeds. Consider the market for seeds. The
Bt varieties of cotton and corn or the Roundup ready soybeans are distinct classes by
themselves. However, some competition is possible because some varieties have been
developed to suit specific agricultural climatic zones. Even so it was observed that only a
few firms dominate the market. For all practical purposes, the fine division achieved in
conventional hybrid technologies will not be possible in biotechnology due to the high fixed
costs of adaptations. The more important problem has been the tying of sales of seed with
other fertilizers etc. produced by the same firm. This effectively reduces the number of
competing firms in the market. Competition is from the producers of conventional hybrid
varieties though their technology is different. The difficult question to address is whether
the demand side relationships and/or the technical relationships should form the basis for
defining the industry boundaries.
Given the preferences of the consumers, say, toward non-GM varieties of crops so long
as they are available it would appear that the markets for GM and non-GM crops are distinct.
However, the costs of labeling non-GM foods increases their cost and make GM crops more
competitive at the margin. Taking GM and non-GM firms together to define an industry will
perhaps be more reliable.
Some authors seem to feel that some biotechnology firms, especially NBFs, may be
dealing only with intermediate level technologies. They may sell their products, contract
with seed companies, or form joint ventures. The definition of markets and products to be
included in the definition are subjective.
Roijakkers et al. (2005) argued that biotechnology industry is characterized by a dual
market structure. On the one hand a group of large, integrated, international and established
companies and on the other hand, a group of relatively small, specialized firms. In the usual
industrial organization literature there will be competition within the two groups but nothing
between them. In biotechnology industry the competition among large firms to force linkages
with smaller firms is significant. Since learning effects are not very strong there may be no
longer term alliances. Instead, there will be many short term contracts.
The boundaries for defining the level at which a market should be conceptualized is, as
yet, a pragmatic choice depending on the purpose of analysis. In general, either technological
and/or demand relationships determine the final choice.

6.2 DEFINING MARKET CONCENTRATION


Historically, the interest in market structure arises from the fact that the monopoly power
of firms determines prices of products and welfare losses. The elasticity of demand, number
of firms, four firm concentration ratios (based on market share of sales), and the Herfindhal
index have been utilized.
100 Economics of Biotechnology

It is well known that the Lerner measure of monopoly power


L = (p – MC)/ p = 1/η
depends on the elasticity of demand. The market structure can be characterized as a monopoly
if η is low. This measure enables the analyst to consider various degrees of monopoly power.
Intuitively, the larger the number of firms the lower the concentration or the higher the
degree of competition. Hence, the number of firms (or numbers equivalents as defined
below) has been utilized to characterize the market structure.
Either due to economies of scale, the degree of diversification, or the economies of being
established in the market, some firms tend to be big even when a large number of small firms
exist in the market. This is typical of the biotechnology industry. For, as observed earlier, a
fairly large number of small NBFs begin to explore the potential to commercially exploit a
scientific discovery. The successful firms, among these, will either merge with or are taken over
by the large seed and chemical companies eventually. Studies by Ricabboni and Pamolli (2002)
consider these issues fairly exhaustively. The purport of this argument is that a few large firms
may have all the effective market power even when the market has a large number of firms.
The market share of the four largest firms is usually called the four-firm concentration ratio
(CR4). Assume that the market consists of n identical firms. The market share of each of them
will be 1/n and CR4 = 4/n. Consequently, n = 4/CR4 can be considered as the numbers
equivalent in any general setting.
The Herfindhal index of concentration utilizes the market shares more explicitly. Let si;
i = 1, 2,…, n denote the market share of the ith firm. Then, the Herfindhal index of concentration
is defined as
H = Σsi2
Observe that if s1 = 1 and si = 0 for i ≠ 1 this measure reduces to H = 1. On the other hand,
if si = 1/n for all i, H = 1/n. In general, 1/H is also a numbers equivalent concentration
measure.
Pharmaceutical firms may have a market advantage if they are highly diversified. This
may arise in one of two ways. First, by producing a variety of products they may experience
economies of scope in demand (this will be considered in detail in the next section). In
effect, they may be able to save on costs of promotion and may reach physicians more
effectively if they have a diversified product range. Second, the advantages may be in the
costs of production if there are economies of scope. That is, by spreading the fixed costs
over a wider range of outputs the firm may be in a position to lower the prices of their
products. A Herfindhal index of diversification will be useful in the first context. To take
the production economies into account define s i = share of the ith product in the variable
cost of the firm.
Then, a similar Herfindhal index would indicate that a high value of H cannot provide much
of an advantage to the firm.
In the context of biotechnology many NBFs may not be producing any final product.
They may still have some monopoly power while dealing with large firms. Conversely, a
Market Structure and Pricing 101

large firm that has extensive technological and/or financial links with NBFs will have
advantages in dealing with them as well as in the markets for final outputs. Roijakkers et
al. (2005) characterize these as dual market structures. Basically the monopoly power of the
large firm and the small firms is in their respective specialization and core competence. The
number of links and the concentration of links may then characterize the market structure.
The strength of the links may be measured by the number of patents or the finances offered
as the case may be. Since the number of large firms in downstream markets is lower this
type of concentration tends to increase while moving toward final product links.
It is quite clear that large chemical firms have advantages with respect to technical
expertise, regulatory links, and finances (deep pockets and ability to take risks). These
features may enable them to undertake a larger number of clinical trials of drugs for eventual
regulatory approval. An ex ante measure of the concentration of clinical trials may then be
a good measure of ex post market power.
Field trials have the same function in the context of agricultural biotechnology. A large
seed firm that is currently undertaking a large number of field trials for a variety of crops
has the prospect of achieving greater market advantage by offering a more diversified
product range.
Though a number of other finer points can be included in the construction of concentration
indices this analysis captures the essential aspects of the degree of concentration in
biotechnology markets.

6.3 SOURCES OF CONCENTRATION


The sale of biotechnology gene components and cells are highly concentrated only because
they are still under patent protection. However, more genes, owned by more NBFs, are
entering the market thereby reducing concentration to some extent. With more licensing,
compulsory or otherwise, the concentration in the downstream industries will reduce further.
See, for instance, Schimmelpfenig (2004).
In very general terms concentration may be a result of economies of scale in the
production process. Biotechnology research activities have been generally rather expensive.
Hence, the large seed companies are basically a result of the desire to spread the costs of
biotechnology over a wide range of output and the market. A natural monopoly like
situation appears to operate. In the pharmaceutical market such advantages seem to be for
products in specific therapeutic categories and for a limited time. The large fixed costs are
also the reason for the emergence of scope economies. These may be related to production
technology or to market demand. In general, as Malerba and Orsenigo (2002) pointed out,
biotechnology innovations are not cumulative in so far as the development of one gene
or protein does not create any advantages in developing another. Even so firms tend to
diversify into a variety of gene and product discoveries in the hope that they can spread
fixed costs over a diversified range of products. The technological economies of scope that
a firm can hope to achieve are rather severely limited.
102 Economics of Biotechnology

In the agricultural biotechnology context small companies have been able to operate
on lower costs and develop niche markets for the product traits that they discover.
However, the large chemical companies increasingly find that biotechnology based seed
production generally complements the use of their chemical fertilizers, pesticides, and
so on. For example, the herbicide tolerant roundup ready soybean production requires
more of the compatible herbicide. Thus, the production of both may impart certain
economies of scale and scope. In the context of insect resistant Bt varieties of corn, cotton,
etc. the chemical company experiences a reduction in the use of chemical insecticides.
The production of Bt varieties of seeds, however, spread the fixed costs giving rise to
some economies of scope. In general, as Just and Heuth (1993) and Malerba and Orsenigo
(2002) remarked, technology related economies of scope do not appear to be the major
reason for product diversification of the large chemical companies.
A more plausible explanation is the economies of scope in demand. As Just and Heuth
(1993) argued, scope economies in demand can be said to materialize if the firm can
generate greater net profits by marketing two or more products together. In the
pharmaceutical market certain chemical and biotechnology related products complement
each other. This is especially valid in the context of diagnostic kits and drug cocktails for
the treatment of AIDS. The other major source is the nature of physician prescriptions,
public health schemes, and promotional activities of large firms. The chemical and seed
firms in agricultural biotechnology area derive advantages from tie-in sales of biotechnology
related seeds and chemical supplements. In the early stages of biotechnology innovation
small firms, operating in niche segments, dominated the market. However, with subsequent
developments it has become profitable for large firms to diversify so that they can take
advantage of the economies of scope in demand. This tends to increase the concentration
in the industry.

6.4 MONOPOLY POWER AND PRICING


Recent studies of the effect of monopoly power on the pricing of products tend to
consider a market in which n firms produce and market homogeneous or very closely
substitutable products. Subramanian (1995) and Watal (1996) are cases in point. To illustrate
their essential argument consider a market with n firms. Let Yi the output of firm i; i =
1,2,…,n. Assume that the market demand curve is
p=a–Y
where
p = price per unit of Y
Y = ΣYi = total output sold by the n firms
Postulate that the cost of production of the ith firm is
Ci = c i Y i
Market Structure and Pricing 103

Assume, further, that the firms are Cournot rivals. That is, they maximize profits by choosing
their output taking the outputs of all other firms as parametric. The profit for the ith firm is then
πi = Yi (a – ΣYi) – ciYi
= (a – ci)Yi – YiΣYi
The profit maximizing choice of Yi satisfies the equation
(a – ci) – Yi – ΣYi = 0
Summing over all i yields
na – Σci – (n+1) ΣYi = 0
Therefore,
ΣYi = an/(n + 1) – Σci/(n + 1)
and, consequently,
Yi = a/(n + 1) + Σci/(n + 1) – ci
p = (a + Σci)/(n + 1)
The Lerner measure of monopoly power of the ith firm is therefore
Li = (p – c)/p
= Yi/p
= (Yi/Y) (Y/p)
= siY/p
where
si = market share of firm i
It should also be noted that the elasticity of demand is
η = – (dY/dp)(p/Y)
= p/Y
Hence, it can be concluded that
Li = si/η
It varies directly with si and inversely with the elasticity of demand. The level of the industry
monopoly power can be represented by
L = ΣsiLi
= H/η
where
H = Herfindhal index of concentration
Consider the more realistic situation in which the products of the n firms are imperfect
substitutes. Let the demand curve for the ith product be
pi = a – bYi – Σ*Yj
104 Economics of Biotechnology

where Σ* is the summation over j≠i = 1,2,…,n


The profit of the ith firm is
πi = (a – ci)Yi – bYi2 – YiΣ*Yj
The profit maximizing Yi, maintaining the assumption of Cournot rivals, satisfies the equation
(a – ci) – 2bYi – Σ*Yj = 0
As before, summation over i results in
na – Σci – 2bΣYi – (n–1) ΣYi = 0
That is, ΣYi = (na – Σci)/ (2b+n–1)
It can be readily verified that
Li = (pi – ci)/pi
= 1/ηi
where ηi is the elasticity of demand for the ith product in Cournot equilibrium. As is evident
it is not possible to define si any longer and it should be no surprise that Li does not depend
on si of any sort.
As biotechnology matures it was noted that the large chemical companies, that originally
produced agricultural chemicals or hybrid seeds, also tend to integrate into biotechnology
based seeds. The usual argument in economic analysis is that such diversification enables
the firm to practice bundling and tying and thereby derive monopoly power and associated
benefit of increased profit. This issue can be best examined through a numerical example.
A general result is of course not available because the phenomenon that will be emphasized
in the following analysis is not universally valid.
To begin with assume that a biotechnology firm is producing seeds (Y1) and a chemical
firm is offering complementary fertilizer/herbicide combinations (Y2). Let the demand curves
for the two products be
p1 = 10 – Y1 + Y2
p2 = 8 + Y1 – Y2
Postulate that the costs of production are
C1 = 5Y1
C2 = Y22
If the two firms operate independently as Cournot rivals their profit maximizing choices will
satisfy the equations
5 – 2Y1 + Y2 = 0
8 + Y1 – 4Y2 = 0
Consequently, the equilibrium output choices will be
Y1 = 4, Y2 = 3
p1 = 11, p2 = 9
Market Structure and Pricing 105

and the total profit that both the firm obtain will be
π = 42
The bundling argument now suggests that the large chemical firm will find it advantageous
to integrate the production of seeds based on biotechnology. This will provide it greater
monopoly power and profit. The integrated firm can be expected to maximize total profits
π = 5Y1 – Y12 + 2Y1Y2 + 8Y2 – 2Y22
The firm therefore chooses
Y1 = 9, Y2 = 6.5
p1 = 7.5, p2 = 10.5
The bundling argument is that the firm will sell the seed and fertilizer together, rather than
independently. The bundle they sell will be
B = 1 unit of Y1 along with 6.5/9 units of Y2
The total profit for the integrated firm will then be
π = 44.5
and the firm gains by such diversification. This tying argument takes the market information
as pivotal to such organizational change.
Suppose, however, that the farmer knows that one unit of Y1 must be combined with one
unit of Y2 to obtain the maximum crop productivity. Then, when the firms are operating
independently, only 3 units of Y1 can be sold. This reduces the combined profit to 31 and leaves
an inventory of 1 unit of output with the firm producing seeds. This also implies a waste of
resources both in the form of capital stock of the firm producing seeds and the variable factors
utilized in production and inventory. It is of course possible that the firms learn over time and
make some correction. However, such coordination is difficult to achieve and expensive. The
integrated firm, that attempts to maximize profits without paying attention to the technical
constraint, faces a similar problem. 2.5 units of Y1 remain in inventory and the profit reduces
to 25.75. Bundling will not be an advantage if the constraint is neglected. It is reasonable to
argue that the diversified firm has the ability to obtain the technical information and the
managerial expertise to utilize it in its decision process. Under these assumptions the production
constraint is
B = 1 unit of Y1 combined with 1 unit of Y2
The corresponding price per bundle will be 18. The profit function can now be written as
π = 13B – B2
so that the optimal production choice is
Y1 = 6.5 = Y2
The profit for the firm is now 42.25. Tying agreements of this nature can be implemented
by a diversified firm to its advantage. However, note that it reduces resource use (or optimize
it) so that society also stands to gain.
106 Economics of Biotechnology

The tendency in economic analysis is to condemn such monopoly practices. However,


as the above analysis indicates, a certain amount of caution is necessary. For, the advantages,
to the society, of the optimal resource use may outweigh the redistribution of the value to
the firm.
It is rather clear from the foregoing analysis that firms in the biotechnology industry will
have some market power. They may also experience higher costs. Due to one or the other
of these factors the market price will be high. However, this does not necessarily imply that
there is always a loss in social welfare. Instead, the efficient welfare maximizing choices
depend on the demand and cost conditions of the specific case. Sweeping generalizations
can be quite misleading.

6.5 DIFFERENTIAL PRICING


Studies dealing with pricing of biotechnology products, and pharmaceutical products in
general, concluded that the monopoly power granted by the IPR regime generally makes the
prices higher. Some of them believe that poorer consumers, especially in the developing
countries, will be deprived of life saving drugs because their ability to pay is low. Differential
pricing arguments have been set up against this background. The primary argument is that
markets should be segmented on the basis of their ability to pay and different prices set up
in the two (or more) segmented markets. Three distinct formulations are discernible. They
will be considered in turn.
Assume that the market can be segmented into two different elasticity zones. It is normally
expected that the more vulnerable section of the consumers will have larger elasticity of
demand. Suppose, now, that the firm maximizes profits by offering different prices in the
two segments of the market. Let
p1 = f (Y1)
p2 = g (Y2)
represent the two demand curves. Similarly, assume that
C = c (Y1+Y2)
is the cost function. Then, profit maximization requires that
MR1 = MR2 = MC
where
MR1 = marginal revenue in market 1
= p1 (1 – 1/η1)
MR2 = p2(1 – 1/η2) and
MC = marginal cost
Consequently, the prices are such that
p1/p2 = (1–1/η1)/(1 – 1/η2)
Market Structure and Pricing 107

Therefore, the firm charges a lower price in the market where the elasticity of demand is
higher.
The following exception should be noted. Assume that the market demand curves are
p1 = 10 – Y1
p2 = 20 – Y2
Let the cost of production be
C = 0.5 (Y1 + Y2)2
It can be readily verified that the profit maximizing choices of the firm are
Y1 = 0, Y2 = 6.67, p = 13.33, and
π = 66.7
when the firm charges the same price from all the consumers. If the firm does discriminate,
its choices will become
Y1 = 1.25, Y2 =6.25,
p1 = 8.75, p2 = 13.75, and
π = 58 (approximately)
This does not increase profits for the firm. The firm will not cater to the segment where the
willingness to pay is lower.
The low ability to pay does not necessarily mean greater elasticity. Instead, it may only
mean a shift to the left with the same elasticity. Does the firm charge a lower price in the market
where the willingness to pay is lower? Let the demand curves in the two markets be
p1 = 10Y1–1/2
p2 = 20Y2–1/2
Suppose the cost of production is
C = 5 (Y1+Y2)
It can be verified that the optimal choice for the firm is
Y1 = 1, Y2 = 4, p1 = 10 = p2
The ability for price discrimination is essentially due to the differences in the elasticity of
demand whether or not it reflects the ability to pay.
One further aspect should be kept in perspective. Suppose a MNC is producing output
at its home base and catering to both the home market and a foreign market. Then, price
discrimination, as described above, occurs. However, note that the MNC has the option of
producing in the foreign country where the costs of production may be lower. This, in itself,
may enable it to offer a lower price in the foreign market. Some organizational issues should
be taken into account for this possibility to materialize. These will be considered in the sequel.
The other two formulations are based on welfare maximization. Consider Fig.5. Clearly,
a monopoly firm will offer output at price pm. This maximizes its profit so long as it cannot
108 Economics of Biotechnology

discriminate between consumers. However, the welfare maximizing choice of output, Yw, can
be restored if the firm offers the additional output at a price pw. The firm would be willing
to offer it so long as the area ABC is positive and the markets are kept segmented; i.e., output
YmYw will not be sold once again to the rest of the market. As noted earlier there is a necessity
for suitable organizational arrangements to achieve this.

p,MC
pm MC
A
pw B
C
D

MR
O Tm Yw Y

Fig. 5
Ganslandt et al. (2001) argued that MC based pricing may not adequately cover the fixed
costs of R&D. Therefore, they suggest that an organization, like the WHO, should create a
fund that will reimburse pharmaceutical firms the entire sunk costs incurred in drug
development. The above analysis does not fully support this viewpoint. However, an
appropriate empirical evaluation is necessary to concretely assert that differential pricing
suggested above will be adequate.
Ramsey pricing goes a step further. It seeks to maximize consumer utility subject to a
zero profit constraint. Consider the problem
Y1 Y2
Max ∫ f(y1) dy1 + ∫ g(y2) dy2
0 0
subject to
Y1f(Y1) + Y2g(Y2) – C(Y1+Y2) = 0
Using the conventional Lagrange multiplier method the first order conditions for maximum
yields
f/g = [f( 1 – 1/η1) – c1]/ [g(1 – 1/η2) – c2]
so that f and g satisfy the equation
c1(1/g – 1/f) = 1/η1 – 1/η2, or
f/g = η2/η1
i.e., a higher price will be charged in the market with a lower elasticity of demand. However,
this is much more difficult to implement. For, unlike the previous two cases the firm is not
willing to adopt this scheme voluntarily (to maximize its profit).
Market Structure and Pricing 109

Danzon (1997, 1998) considered the application of this principle to cover sunk costs. The
following salient points may be recorded.
• Ramsey pricing assumes a zero monopoly profits (a normal rate of return allowed).
Hence, it is necessary to have a regulated price regime to implement such pricing.
A free market operation will resist its use.
• In the international context it is not possible to have a coordinated regulatory
process for price fixation. In fact, some countries, that do not want to pay any part
of the sunk costs, may negotiate lower prices.
• From an operational viewpoint, regulated price regimes rarely produce meaningful
information on the elasticities of demand. The basic foundation of Ramsey pricing
may not be available to the regulator even within a given country.
Watal (2000,2001) examined some of the institutional issues involved in the implementation
of differential pricing. The following two are crucial.
• It may be necessary to label the products for each of the markets. The colors used
for drugs may be one such marker. Size and packing have been utilized extensively
to delimit the markets. On the other hand, lower priced drugs may be available
through public health schemes with the definite understanding that the physicians
will provide them only to the poorer sections of the population.
• When trading is across national boundaries the low income country should be
expected to guarantee that the low priced drugs will not be reexported. This can
be covered under the WTO agreements. The issue of parallel imports has drawn
considerable attention. See, for example, Maskus (2001) and Scherer and Watal
(2001). A few details will be taken up in the next chapter. Suppose the MNC allows
production in a low income country. Of course, technical capability is a prerequi-
site. In addition, the MNC needs a guarantee that its proprietary technology is safe
and that low priced drugs will not be exported. Appropriate institutional arrange-
ments will be necessary to make differential pricing successful.
The other thorny aspect is the nature of differential prices. For, under the transfer pricing
regulations trade across national boundaries the lower prices
• cannot be rationalized on the basis of the argument that costs of production are
lower than comparable products in the foreign country
• should not be such as to provide a greater rate of profit than comparable products
in the foreign country
• should not result in a rate of return on capital in excess of that prevalent in the
foreign country
Appendix 2 contains a more detailed analysis of these transfer pricing rules.
The other problem that has been receiving attention is reference pricing. Suppose a large
firm offers a drug at a low price in a developing country. The consumers in the patent country
of the firm want justification for why they are paying much higher prices. In other words,
differential pricing limits the monopoly pricing power of the firm in all its markets.
110 Economics of Biotechnology

On the whole, it can be concluded that at least in the short run until patent protection
is exhausted it would be worthwhile to put some differential pricing in operation. This
practice is already in existence with respect to TB and AIDS drugs.

6.6 DYNAMIC PRICING


The above two sections considered the pricing problem from a static perspective. However,
two dynamic effects have been brought to light indicating that the actual prices may be lower.
First, it was noted that the adoption of GM varieties involve wide ranging changes in
production practices. Consider the case of herbicide resistant roundup ready soybeans. These
seeds allow no-till planting of crops and a higher density per hectare. As a result the
machinery used for planting as well as spraying pesticide are different. Further, once the
investments in the machinery are made they cannot be used elsewhere. That is, they are
irreversible and sunk. The only way to recover the cost is by repeated use over time.
Consequently, the firms try to avoid the possible loss of future market that may result from
static monopoly pricing. In other words, pricing practices recognize the changing market
over time and the fixed costs. The monopoly power of the seed producer will also decrease
as a result. See, for example, Perrin and Fulginiti (2001), Demont et al. (2004), and Weaver
and Wessler (2004).
Second, in the pharmaceutical sector it was generally observed that, contrary to
expectations, the prices are lower when a drug is under patent but increases once the generic
drugs enter the market after the expiry of the patent. Bhattacharya and Vogt (2003) explain
this in the following manner. Note that the physicians determine the demand for therapeutics
in general. They find it costly to learn about new drugs constantly. The pharmaceutical
companies tend to set up promotional campaigns that maximize the stock of information and
experience with the doctors as a priority over static monopoly pricing. For, they wish to
ensure a large market share before the generics enter the market. After the expiry of the
patent the branded drug loses its more elastic segment of the market to competitive generics.
However, the stock of goodwill that they accumulated with the physicians allows
pharmaceutical firms to charge higher prices for their branded drugs. To an extent such price
increases will also be necessary to recover the costs of promotion incurred earlier.

6.7 IN RETROSPECT
Most biotechnology based products are in their early stages. As yet they are sold under
patent protection. Consequently, the market is highly concentrated. A few adaptations of
seeds, to suit different agro-climatic zones may make monopoly severe in specific segments
but reduce it overall. When the patents are off and competition develops it is difficult to
predict the degree of competition that emerges. For, unless costs can be reduced significantly,
smaller market segments may not sustain a large number of competitive varieties. Competition
may be effective only in markets like the diagnostic kits where the investments are low.
Market Structure and Pricing 111

Labeling non-GM products may provide an effective means of discrimination. The increase
in non-GM prices may offer some advantages to the GM varieties though consumer resistance
may still be important.
Gambardella et al. (2000) noted that “the competitiveness of the industry cannot be
assessed by looking at the individual firms, but also at the broader set of institutions,
infrastructures, and policies that influence the actions of companies, and even more important,
at the dynamic interactions between these levels of analysis.”
This page
intentionally left
blank
Chapter 7

ETHICS AND ENVIRONMENT

7.1 ISSUES AT STAKE


Nature has its own rhythms and cycles. They are inadequate to satisfy our requirements. By
their very definition modern technologies, be they mechanical, chemical, or biological, are
such that they try to utilize some features of nature to counter other, albeit undesirable,
properties of nature. This process tends to enhance the welfare of individuals and the society.
Concepts of central heating of homes and offices, air-conditioning, and so on are representative.
However, a central problem in the adoption of any new technology is the urgency, on the part
of private firms, in commercializing technology with the objective of recovering the sunk costs
of R&D and generating profits quickly and over a short time horizon. This may subvert welfare
of the society in general. This is by now widely acknowledged. More significantly, such
commercial greed did not acknowledge the ethical and environmental consequences of the
adoption of such technologies. See, for instance, Dickens (2004). For, in particular, note that
every technology has some negative consequences for welfare. Even so, societies and
individuals
• were compelled to accept the negative effects because there was no other choice
• accepted the consequences of technology because the positive aspects of their pro-
ductivity were overwhelming
• accepted technologies because the negative effects (like environmental degrada-
tion) were not even evident at the beginning (they were evident only after cumu-
lative use)
In a way, ethical and environmental concerns can never be articulated in any objective
and comprehensive manner. Hence, it is not possible to conceptualize a once for all resolution
of such issues. It is, therefore, necessary to be alert to the possibility of negative consequences
114 Economics of Biotechnology

of biotechnology and their economic impact on individuals and the society. It is perhaps
fortuitous that prior information is sought in the context of biotechnology. A brief outline will
be presented keeping this in perspective.

7.2 ETHICAL ISSUES


Consider the case of an individual whose life expectancy at a point of time is 65 years.
Suppose he suddenly becomes seriously ill (ignore the reasons for the present). Assume that
the science of medicine has only one remedy for the ailment and that the longevity reduces by
10 years after the person is cured. Would it be ethically defensible for a doctor to administer
this drug? The economic consequences of either choice may dictate what is ethical.
Dynamite and atomic energy can either improve human welfare or destroy it. It depends
on how we use them. In general, technology itself is free from ethics. See, for example,
Thompson (2000) and Dickens (2004). The ethical question is: should it be used for destructive
purposes?
Consider the issue of genetic feticide (bias against female babies). The current social norm
is for every male to have a life partnership with only one girl. The ethics of sex selection, apart
from the religious overtones, becomes an ethical issue because the one-for-one relationship
cannot be maintained. Is it not possible to change the social norm? Or, will that be unethical in
some absolute sense? A time may come when the balance is against the males. What happens
then?
Mechanical inventions and chemical technologies were at the apex of the industrial
revolution of the 20th century. Modern manufacturing is mostly automated. Each individual
working on the assembly line deals with only a small part of a total product. In the early
stages it was pointed out that this robs the individual of the creative expression involved in
manufacturing the product in its entirety. If a worker is operating only one machine, which
produces a small part of the final product, all the time, he cannot even discern the value of his
activity to the user of the final product. Such mechanization of production alienates him from
the product itself. As Knight (1933, p.21) puts it, “specialization in itself is an evil, measured
by generally accepted human ideals. It gives us more products, but in its effects on human
beings as such it is certainly bad in some respects and in others questionable.”
Automation also reduced the demand for labor. Even this was regarded as unethical. There
is occasional resistance to the use of mechanical contraptions. However, the enormous increase
in productivity, that such technologies provide, tilted the choice in their favor. Societies accepted
the negative consequences as inevitable.
The advent of the green revolution necessitated large land holdings for the effective use of
irrigation, fertilizers, and harvest equipment. Of necessity this meant that some small and
marginal farmers lost their land and may be livelihood that they are accustomed to. Some
considered this displacement to be unethical. However, the productivity increases created an
uneasy truce.
Ethics and Environment 115

Use of chemical technologies created a different kind of problem. For, fertilizer and pesticide
residues in foodstuffs have been recorded. This was perhaps not anticipated when these
technologies were introduced. They are a result of cumulative use. The ethical question is the
amount of such residues that may be deemed acceptable.
Similar ethical issues appear in the context of biotechnology. They continue to persist
because alternatives (conventional chemical technologies) are still available. There is also no
clear evidence of superior productivity of biotechnology. The religious issues and social norm
considerations may appear to hold sway due to this. It is useful to consider them objectively
and keep their economic consequences in perspective.

7.3 ENVIRONMENTAL ISSUES


As noted above most of the ethical issues arise in the context of the impact of the use of a
product or technology on specific individuals. Of course, some ethical issues may also refer to
their impact on society in general. By way of contrast, environmental issues refer to external
effects on individuals, other than the users themselves, of the use of a product or a technology.
Environmental issues have some common features and others that are distinct. In general,
some technological changes may result in unexpected and unwanted consequences; e.g., air
pollution from the use of fossil fuels, effect on soils of excessive fertilizer use in the context of
the green revolution (in particular, the sterility of soils and pest infestation of unexpected
proportions). A few examples will clarify the issues involved.
To make my life comfortable I need some wooden furniture in my house. Trees must be
cut to make them. It is not just I but all others in society want such amenities. More trees are
cut (during a fixed interval of time) in comparison to what nature can regenerate. This process
reduces the oxygen in the air and the green cover against floods, soil erosion etc. The negative
environmental effects, it is said, outweigh the positive economic benefits.
In the final analysis, at any point of time, only a few technological solutions are available to
overcome the pressing problems of the society. The choice may be between extinction now or
extinction tomorrow depending on how technology adapts itself to ever increasing challenges.
As the Nobel laureate James Meade remarked earlier, neither the selfishness of the current
generation nor its altruism may be the best economic solution to environmental concerns.

7.4 ETHICAL ISSUES IN AGRICULTURAL BIOTECHNOLOGY


The ethical concerns can be broadly classified into three groups. They relate to the perception of
• individuals and the effects on them as individuals
• society; some activities are commercially beneficial to the firms but affect the society
adversely, others benefit the society though they are not commercially beneficial
• the duties of the current generation towards posterity
116 Economics of Biotechnology

Assume that there is a shortage of food. This may leave many individuals starving or left
under nourished. Whatever may be the negative effects of GM foods they may help these
individuals to crawl out of this problem. Is it ethical to leave them starving because it is unethical
to use GM foods (this is colorfully reflected in the resentment “there is a gene in my food”)?
The point of the argument is as follows. The use of chemical fertilizers in non-GM foods left
pesticide residues that are harmful. And yet we use them because the alternative of starvation
is not efficient. Can it be conclusively established that the negative effects, on individuals, of
the use of GM foods, are greater? In particular, there is a possibility that GM foods will leave
Bt toxins and other forms of toxins in food. As Altieri and Rosset (1999) pointed out, genetic
modification of seeds and plants may also alter the metabolism of the food producing plant
and make it produce new allergins or toxins. Also see Mizan (2000). Will the toxins be more
harmful to individuals than the pesticide residues? The fragmentary evidences available at
the moment cannot provide any conclusive answer.
However, private firms are mindlessly pushing products and technologies that are
relatively easy to discover. The long run effects of the introduction of GM crops are not clear
as yet.
McGloughlin (1999) and Mizan (2000) also raised the possibility that GM products may
also decrease the production of essential nutrients thus reducing the nutritive and protective
value of food. In particular, it was noted that round up ready soybeans are inferior due to
reduced quantities of isoflavons that are known to be anti-cancer agents. Creating such
disadvantages to individuals, some argue, will in itself be unethical. However, as Robinson
(1999) remarked, “where do divine responsibilities (natural cycles and dependence on them)
end and man’s begin? The dividing line is not clear, and all human endeavor could be said to
interfere with God’s will to some extent.”
Biotechnology applications to the animal world raise some ethical issues. For instance, it
is known that rBST increases production of milk in cows. But it is also claimed that the animals
are at risk because several health problems arise. Since rBST is administered through an injection
this is an in vivo GM technology. Is it ethical to make the animal suffer for interest of humans?
See, for example, Thompson (1999). However, it was pointed out that a certain total feed
management practice will eliminate the problems. It is not used simply because it is too
expensive. There is perhaps a need for certain regulatory practices to eliminate such undesirable
effects of biotechnology. Rejecting them as unethical may not be the most efficient solution.
Similarly, as Giescke et al. (2004) remarked, “genetic improvements of staple crops like
the sweet potato, and cash crops like tea and coffee remain commercially unattractive for
large biotechnology companies. The benefits of poor nations must be addressed by working
on these crops as well.”
A related aspect was noted in Robinson (1999). “Quinova is a traditional crop of the Andes
and the indigenous farmers have been breeding it for the prevailing conditions for centuries.
In 1994 a patent was issued to two U.S. agronomers covering the use of CMS in Bolivian
cultivar ‘Apalena’. Granting a patent on a staple food crop from a poor country to outsiders
sets a dangerous and disturbing precedent and must be regarded as ethically unsound.”
Ethics and Environment 117

Geographic indicators is a contested area of the TRIPS agreement. Article 22.1 defines
them as “ indications which identify a good as originating in the territory of a member, or a
region or locality in that territory, where a given quality, reputation or (some) other
characteristic of the good is (typical) to its geographic origin.” To be more specific, consider
the following. Neem trees can grow in every country. One country calling it neem cannot
prevent others from using the same product (the only thing is that they may have to call it
something else and not neem; that is, the trademark or copyright for the label alone can be
protected legally.) Basmati rice was produced in some parts of India for centuries. Some other
country may now take this variety, produce it, and call it Basmati as well. (Before the mania
for patents developed collecting such samples, exporting them, and cultivating them elsewhere
was common place. Nobody objected. But in the post patent regime even this is a violation.)
Does this give them a right to exclusivity just because it was not patented in India earlier?
TRIPS acknowledges that they can be protected through copyrights and trademarks.
Conventional plant breeding methods developed efficient varieties suitable to specific agro
climatic conditions. For the present biotechnology seeds do not have the same flexibility. Even
so, if the GM varieties replace the conventional non-GM seeds many marginal farmers may
become bankrupt. Recall that this ethical issue was raised in the context of the green revolution
as well.
Of greater concern is the concept of terminator seeds. Traditionally, farmers have been
accustomed to preserving seed for planting the next cycle. In fact, the germplasm of many
countries contain only such robust varieties. At least initially it was felt that biotech seeds will
also be similar. However, some possibilities of a decrease in productivity with repeated use
have been sighted. These natural processes determine the demand for seed at any point of
time. The biotech seed companies feel that this demand is inadequate to maximize their
commercial interest. Monsanto, for example, writes into their contract with their farmers a
requirement that they buy seed every year thereby prohibiting replanting. Worse still, MNCs
created terminator seeds that are sterile and cannot be used for replanting. This is clearly
unethical in that it is not an inbuilt compulsion of technology but an artifact set up to maximize
the profits of large seed companies. The unfavorable distribution of gains, in favor of seed
companies, assumes unethical proportions. For a brief discussion of this issue the reader may
refer to Robinson (1999).
In the U.S. a method for producing corn syrup with high fructose content has been
developed. As a result their imports of sugar from developing countries has gone down. The
question being raised is that any substitution that affects farmers from less developed countries
is unethical. Of course, the answer from the MNCs would be that they must yield if they
cannot be competitive. The argument about other GM crops is also similar both within a country
and across national boundaries. The loss of exports for farmers of developing countries is
unlikely to be acknowledged as unethical.
Consider the case of Round up ready soybeans. Adoption of this variety necessarily
increases the demand for Round up. This gives an opportunity for Monsanto to tie the sales of
seeds and herbicides and tilt the market advantage in its favor. The antitrust arguments consider
this unethical because it is anti competitive.
118 Economics of Biotechnology

One thing is by now clear. The private commercial interests of some individuals may be in
conflict with the personal interests and welfare of other individuals. The following issues are
pertinent in a broader social context.
• Unequal access to individuals
• Equity in the distribution of gains
• Loss of livelihood from traditional knowledge
As noted earlier, non-GM foods are as yet available in adequate quantities. Hence, there is
no pressure to use GM foods. Ethical questions are debated only because the cushion of non-
GM foods is available. What happens when the demand out strips their availability? Will the
answers to the ethical questions change when this happens?
In the final analysis, when it comes to adverse effects of biotechnology on individuals, the
primary ethical concern is their right to information and decision. See, for instance, Gesche et
al. (2004). No other recommendation can be justified on any objective basis.

7.5 ETHICAL ISSUES IN DRUG DEVELOPMENT


Consider the context of cancer and other severe diseases. Assume that an in vitro test becomes
available. A doctor knows that there will be an adverse emotional impact if the result of the test is
positive and revealed to the patient. Should such tests be allowed at all? What if they are conducted
after taking the patient’s consent? It can even be argued that such knowledge may have a positive
impact on the individual and his welfare since he can take adequate precautions and/or rearrange
his activities. Issues related to birth control, gender identification of fetus, and designer babies
belong to the same category. However, as Dickens (2004) argued, parents may be able “to spare
their children from natural chance or lottery of individual genetic constitution.” The other side of
the argument is that such advantages subvert goals of equality of opportunity in society. This is an
ethical dilemma. In vivo tests may be more harmful. The ethical concerns may then be genuine.
For, as Oh (2002) remarked, if the investigator (who is doing the clinical tests) administers the
drug, without prior consent of the patient, the principle of individual autonomy and rights will be
broken. However, as he pointed out, taking consent may impact social welfare adversely. For, the
testing process may get delayed for lack of volunteers. The efficient trade off between individual
and social welfare cannot be defined in any objective manner.
The question being raised is the following. Suppose, in the natural course of events,
someone gets sick. It would be ethically defensible if a biotechnology drug is used to cure
such a patient. However, it would be ethically wrong if similar drugs are used on a normal,
healthy person to enhance performance. As Dickens (2004) puts it, it would be morally
indefensible to administer memory blocking drugs that result in socially irresponsible but
self-satisfied behavior of individuals. (Recall that we regularly test athletes for the use of
performance enhancing drugs).
It is by now well known that patients in developing countries, who are suffering from
severe diseases like cancer, cannot afford the prices charged by the MNCs. Part of the reason
Ethics and Environment 119

may be that they pay the costs on their own in the absence of any comprehensive national
health plan or insurance coverage. How should this issue be addressed? Who should? Let the
governments of the developing countries take the responsibility is the answer from the MNCs.
Some issues, noted earlier in the context of agricultural biotechnology, can be discerned
here as well. For example, the MNCs tend to ask firms in developing countries to do clinical
testing of potentially hazardous drugs. The private firms in developing countries fall prey to
this in the interest of making profits. They pay scant attention to the negative effects on human
beings.
The MNCs, preoccupied with maximizing profits from their R&D efforts, do not pay
attention to the development of drugs for malaria, Hepatitis B etc. prevalent in developing
countries. Clearly, there has been an unequal access to the benefits of biotechnology in the
early stages of development so far. (Note that similar accusations regarding other technologies
are possible.)

7.6 ENVIRONMENTAL ISSUES


One of the positive aspects of biotechnology is the prospect of bioremediation. The
following observations are pertinent.
• Microorganisms have been created to clean up environmentally obnoxious mate-
rials such as engine oil. They were useful in cleaning up oil spills. This technique
was utilized at Haldia and Mathura refineries recently.
• Biologically altered production methods for indigo, for instance, turned out to be
environmentally safer. Common colon bacterium E.coli has been engineered to
synthesize indigo. The biotech indigo is indistinguishable from synthetic chemical
material in handling dye-mix preparations and performs as efficiently.
• To the extent GM crops have resistance to common pests, the use of conventional
pesticide is reduced and consequently the associated pollution (in fact, it was held
that frequent spraying of conventional pesticides has been harmful to the health
of the farmers and their families as well. This was noted in Schaal (2004)).
• Reduction in the use of chemical fertilizers and irrigation water, to the extent they
are possible, will assist in reducing environmental pollution
• GM bacteria have been utilized as bio-sensors for detecting land mines
• Genetically modified plants have the capacity to isolate and separate toxic sub-
stances. These plants are sown as a lawn and the resulting plants harvested and
disposed off as toxic waste.
See, for example, Schaal (2004), Mizan (2000), Khan et al. (2004).
Schaal (2004) also noted that Bt produces a family of crystalline proteins that inhibit insect
growth. These cry proteins are considered environmentally friendly insecticide. In fact, the
bacterium is used as a natural insecticide in organic farming.
120 Economics of Biotechnology

While there are some beneficial aspects of biotechnology a number of environmental issues
have been brought to light. Most of these are in the context of agricultural biotechnology.
They generally address the following issues.
• When pests and herbs are reduced as a result of the GM varieties there is every
chance that birds and animals will be affected. For, this results in less food and
cover for insects and bird species higher up the food chain that feed on weeds and
insects. The use of pesticides and the resulting loss of feed for birds and animals
may affect biodiversity adversely
• Transmission through air may result in contamination of nearby farms as well. The
potential transfer through the flow of genes from herbicide resistant crops to wild
or semi-domesticated relatives can lead to the creation of super weeds.
• The use of irrigation water and the runoff into neighboring fields and sources of
drinking water have negative effects on the population at large. The genetic ma-
terial may be transmitted through irrigation flow. When agricultural inputs flow
into the surrounding farm lands the possibility of aggressive insect populations
finding their way into these farm lands increases. The potential transfer through
the flow of genes from herbicide resistant crops to wild or semi-domesticated
relatives can lead to the creation of super weeds.
• At the end of a cropping season the remaining GM plants are ploughed into the
soil. This may change the genetic makeup of the farm as well as the neighboring
farms. The use of Bt crops affects non-target organisms and ecological processes.
Bt toxin present in crop foliage plowed under harvest can adhere to the soil colloids.
This affects the invertebrate populations in the soil that breakdown organic matter
and fulfils other ecological roles
• There is a potential for herbicide resistant varieties to become serious weeds in
other crops
• The loss of soil nutrients and creation of more and vigorous pests
• There is a possibility that vector recombination generates new virulent strains of
viruses, especially in transgenic plants engineered for viral resistance with viral
genes. Recombination between RNA and a viral RNA inside the transgenic crop
may produce a new pathogen leading to more severe disease problems. This was
noted in Altieri and Rosset (1999).
Consider these issues in turn.

• Some species survive beyond the plantation period. Whenever these plants contain
herbicide resistant genes, the risk that such species survive beyond crop cycles and
pollinate with weeds around farming areas is high. Such uncontrolled cross pollination
is the main reason for the rise of herbicide resistant weeds. These resistant weeds then
invade natural plant communities beyond farms. See, for example, Sampath (2004).
• Biotechnology derived species might affect non-target organisms. For instance,
wind blown pollen from crops may affect natural surroundings. In particular, it was
reported that Bt pollen kills monarch butterflies.
Ethics and Environment 121

• The existence of pests on a farm helps birds and other species like butterflies to
thrive. Pest control through Bt varieties cuts this off. It is possible that there will
be a net increase relative to the conventional system in the amount of wildlife early
in the growing season in the GM treatment (arising from the opportunity to leave
spraying until later in the season) but a net relative decrease (due to the efficiency
with which weeds are removed) later in the season, after the broad spectrum
herbicide is applied. As yet it is difficult to determine which of these two effects
predominate. Assessing concomitant effects on other organisms is, at best, hazard-
ous. Often, the new GM varieties crossed on their own with local landraces and
native species. This has a profound effect on biodiversity, by altering agricultural
practices, by introducing species that displaced native species or by altering com-
munity dynamics. Sometimes whole sections of chromosomes are transferred in-
troducing genes that may produce undesirable traits like early dropping of seed
or reduced crop yield. See, for example, Schaal (2004).
• The production of weedy hybrids is another concern. The worry is that when a GM
crop hybridizes with a wild ancestor, the hybrid offspring will lead to the formation
of a vigorous weed. Hybrids have an enhanced fitness and are resistant to attack
by some lepidopterons. Bt hybrids have greater seed production thus raising the
specter of gene flow altering both the gene pool and providing a new weedy taxon.
With this hindsight there are environmental concerns in the use of biotechnology. As of
now most of these effects are speculative. It must also be noted that not all environmental
effects of biotechnology are bad. In particular, techniques of bioremediation also have the
prospect of cleaning up chemical pollution. Caution may be justified. It would be worthwhile
to examine the possibilities and their economic consequences further.

7.7 INTERNATIONAL CONVENTIONS


Note that the ethical issues are generally of two types. They are either biodiversity related
or they pertain to the unequal distribution of gains among participants in a given country or
across different countries in their trading relations. Similarly, issues of biosafety may relate to
the effects of biotechnology products on individuals or environmental problems as they pertain
to societies in general or across international boundaries in the context of international trade.
The pertinent questions are as follows.
• Since each country is sovereign in its decision making it can put some regulations
in place to protect its citizens. What actions have individual countries taken in this
regard? How efficiently are these regulations implemented?
• International trade is governed, in recent years, by protocols like the WTO agree-
ments and the Commission on Biodiversity. To what extent do these regulations
address the issues involved? Are they adequate to address the issues of concern?
To begin with notice that by now almost all countries have rigorous procedures for field
trials and approval of crops and clinical trials and regulatory approval for drugs and diagnostic
122 Economics of Biotechnology

kits. However, there are sharp differences. For example, in the U.S. the tolerance limit for
genetic materials is 5 percent whereas in the European Union it is 1 percent. This lack of
uniformity should be expected across different countries. It does not pose any problem for
domestic transactions. However, it becomes a bottleneck if trading across nations is
conceptualized. On the other hand, the WTO insists on scientific evidence as the only
determining factor. According to this principle other countries cannot deny use and trade in
GM products if one country has produced scientific evidence about its safety. The only redressal
available is through the grievance committee of the WTO. However, the WTO arrangements
are conditioned more by the profit making implications of private firms rather than the ethical
and environmental concerns of member countries. It is unlikely that a consensus can be reached
on any uniform standards that need to be adhered to. Can there be any other mechanism for
reconciliation?
The following details about the regulatory environment as it pertains to biodiversity and
biosafety have already been recorded in chapter 3. They will be recalled here to place the
argument in a proper perspective.
The Convention on Biodiversity (CBD) and Cartagena Protocol (2003) are the most
pertinent. The goals of CBD are the
• conservation of biodiversity
• sustainable use of its components
• fair and equitable sharing of benefits
• appropriate access to and transfer of relevant technologies and products
To pursue these objectives CBD
• recognizes sovereignty of countries and their genetic resources
• focuses on in situ (within the body) conservation of genetic resources (not in gene
banks)
• recommends protection of technical knowledge
The Cartagena Protocol deals mostly with international trade. It emphasizes the need for
• an adequate level of protection and monitoring of transboundary movements to
ensure safe transfer, handling, and the use of genetic materials
• minimizing risks for human health and environment
The following approaches have been suggested.
• Prior informed consent (based on scientific knowledge and tests); the exporting
country should inform the importing state of the nature and hazards of shipping
GM products and obtain written consent
• Importing countries have a right to refuse such consignments if they are not sat-
isfied about safety or destroy the lot if illegally shipped
The WTO is a multinational trade organization focusing primarily on mechanisms for free
trade across national boundaries. Environmental problems of common concern to all countries
will be a subject of consideration under WTO regulations. But if one country declares a product
Ethics and Environment 123

safe others cannot reject it. Similarly, under the WTO agreements all varieties of a product
will be treated alike. Countries cannot discriminate between them on the argument that they
are not local varieties that suit their agro climatic conditions. However, many countries feel
that biotechnology related seeds offer few varieties. They are not necessarily tailored to suit
the great variety of argo economic climates that we experience. The vast array of old varieties,
obtained through conventional breeding will become useless if they are not utilized for a long
time. Switching to biotechnology may result in both these types of losses due to reduced
biodiversity. Most countries find both these aspects disturbing. However, the preoccupation
with trade renders any discrimination on this basis as a non-trade barrier under the WTO
configuration. To reach an agreement on high enough standards may avoid clashing with
trade related issues but it is difficult to achieve it.
The Cartagena Protocol allows individual country governments to discriminate on the
basis of safety and environmental concerns. This clashes with WTO agreements. That is why
the U.S.A. and EU did not sign the Cartegena Protocol. For all practical purposes they say that
non-trade barriers are not acceptable to them.
The question being raised is this. If countries are sovereign in their decision making will
they not impose different constraints? Some of them may be considered legitimate in the
interests of biodiversity and safety. Others may be deemed as rules to protect trade and local
enterprises against invasion by MNCs. How to distinguish between these two? Whose decisions
should be honored? WTO principles claim to depend on scientific principles that cannot be
refuted by any one country. Others claim that this is not enough because there are still issues
about the quantum of damage that is acceptable to any one country. This may have to be
weighed against the loss in trade itself. Differences in judgment create an impasse.
The WTO has a dispute settlement mechanism designed to deal with disagreements
between members over interpretations. Further, the committee on Trade and Environment of
the WTO recognizes potential conflicts between trade liberalization objectives and
environmental protection objectives. However, they tend to give a greater emphasis to trade
related matters. In contrast, the Convention on Biosafety is a multilateral environmental
agreement without a clear mechanism to settle a dispute if an exporting country disagrees
with a unilateral trade barrier imposed by the party of import. This, as well as other related
issues, have been considered exhaustively in Isaac et al. (2001).
The problem is to find a way of resolving the contradiction between the goals of WTO and
the Cartegena Protocol. Voluntary labeling of GM products, to identify market demand for
specific types, came as a result of this. What it means is that, even before the regulators (country
governments) in the importing country ask for a test, the firm in the exporting country will
declare the biological content. The other alternative is to set up a uniform stringent standard
for everybody to follow. This may not be quite acceptable under the issue of biodiversity.
From the viewpoint of economic analysis there is a necessity to clearly define the tradeoff
between the needs for food and welfare as opposed to the advantages of a cleaner environment.
124 Economics of Biotechnology

However, this is not likely to emerge so long as non-GM varieties of food are available in
sufficient quantities.
Note that some ethical issues, especially those related to unequal access of biotechnology
to the less developed countries, have not been addressed adequately. The only mechanism
currently in place is differential pricing. Perhaps the only way out is for individual countries
to formulate suitable policies for themselves. The MNCs and international trade regimes are
unlikely to address them.
One point should be clear by now. The issues of ethics and environment raised are common
to almost all technologies. To claim that biotechnology effects are devastating is an exaggeration.

7.8 LESSONS AND CONTROL


There is a justifiable concern that current field biosafety tests tell us little about potential
risks associated with commercial scale production of transgenic crops. A main concern is that
international pressures to gain markets and profits is resulting in firms releasing GM crops
too fast and without consideration for their long term impacts on people or the ecosystem.
Ascertaining the associated social costs and controlling the negative effects has hardly
begun. Put in a different way
• There are several directions in which biotechnology developments are progressing
• Only some of them can be said to enhance social value
• Significant negative effects are possible in the use of certain technologies
It would perhaps be more prudent to obtain reasonably complete information before
granting regulatory approvals. Unfortunately, the commercial greed and economic power of
a few large corporations may be forcing early introduction of varieties that may lead to
undesirable effects over the long haul.
The efficient response will not be despair. Nor should it be advisable to throw the baby
with the bath water. Instead, the need is for greater caution, proper regulation, and policy
reforms that curb or reduce the deleterious effects.
In particular, it is necessary to educate farm workers about
• safe ways of spraying
• disposal of pesticide containers
• practices of integrated pest management
See, Gupta and Chandak (2004).
Ethics and Environment 125

Chapter 8

GOVERNMENT POLICY

8.1 AN OVERVIEW
R&D, whether it is scientific knowledge or applied science, materializes only when
• individuals in the society are motivated to do it
• obtain the necessary support (including the receipt of the associated rewards) from
private firms and/or the government
• the social and organizational culture is favorable to it
In some countries, especially based on private enterprise, there is adequate R&D culture.
However, in our case, there is hardly any culture of private R&D in the industrial sector.
Instead, there is excessive dependence on public institutions and government funding to carry
out R&D.
It is generally agreed that some R&D activities have a public good nature. For example,
the road network for transportation, and defense related activities (at least until the activity
reaches a mature stage, e.g., the internet). The government must generally finance such
R&D.
Some activities, such as
• agricultural extension services
• public health and insurance schemes to cover the disadvantaged sections of the
society require public funding on a continuing basis. Such public financing of
national health schemes may augment the demand for private goods (medicines)
and their appropriability.
• A similar argument suggests that defense based public investment has spillover
effects on private investment
126 Economics of Biotechnology

In general, public investment and/or financing may affect the supply of goods as well as the
demand for them.
In the initial phase of development of some industries the government has another
fundamental role. Apart from financing private research it has to support public institutions
that undertake research. This is basically due to the lack of appropriability of research despite
its contribution to social welfare.
Stated somewhat more generally, government sponsored research in publicly funded and
managed institutions
•complements private research; there are many socially desirable activities that the
private sector will not take up because they cannot make enough profit. Perforce
the government must find ways of achieving such activities in practice. Similarly,
there are certain activities, like the communication networks, where private invest-
ment becomes profitable only when a critical amount of activity materializes. That
is, public R&D may precede private R&D in order to create a cost effective atmo-
sphere for the later to flourish.
• may be competitive with private research in the context of most biotechnology
activities, and the human genome project in particular. There is an apprehension
that knowledge developed and patented by the private sector will not be readily
available for further developments. Hence, public research may have to be accel-
erated in competition with private research so that the overall stock of knowledge
increases and can be licensed freely to all users.
A very useful approach to these issues can be found in Ishibashi and Matsumara (2005).
However, in areas like the semi conductor devices and biotechnology it was felt that
• they do not have any public good character
• private firms can appropriate (recover costs on the market) the results of their R&D
• Private sector seed companies have been offering extension services and recovering
their costs. There is enough demand because food is a necessity. Hence, public
spending is not necessary
• Patents and IPR protection may be adequate to sustain private R&D spending
• at the most the high risk of initial scientific research may need to be shared by the
government
Public funding of the activity is also considered to be inhibitive because
• too much political intervention curtails the freedom of the scientists to pursue their
curiosities and hence the nature and scope of private R&D
• too much public investment crowds out private initiative and investment.
Appropriability of private investment decreases with the volume of public invest-
ment. For instance, why would a farmer pay for extension services if he gets it free?
There is also a feeling that public financial resources
• would be inadequate in emerging areas like biotechnology
Government Policy 127

• may be directed to areas that will not necessarily be the priority of private firms
In addition, there are problems associated with transferring knowledge from the public research
institutions to the private sector firms. In particular, the
• organizational arrangements (they are very different in these two sectors)
• financial arrangements like licensing or taxation of returns are crucial issues that
determine the efficiency of such transfer.
Since financing has such an important role, it is necessary for the government to
• define its policies with respect to foreign direct investment and foreign institutional
investments
• create an atmosphere wherein venture capital and other financial institutions can
function efficiently (some regulation is necessary even if the government does not
underwrite such activities)
One other aspect of government intervention was deemed to be of crucial importance.
The release of some GM foods and pharmaceuticals may prove hazardous to
• individual consumers
• the society
• the environment
Biosafety and regulation of GM products becomes a crucial issue in such a context. More
generally, the social objectives and definition of socially desirable projects is moving beyond
appropriability and marketability.
In sum, the major issues for government policy pertain to
• production and/or provision of some goods that are socially desirable but for
which private enterprise cannot recover costs efficiently
• financial arrangements that provide a catalytic effect for the development of private
activity or complement private investment
• regulation and control of investment and production in view of the ethical and
environmental implications.
These are the crucial issues for government policy if some details are set aside. The following
sections consider each of these aspects in some detail.

8.2 SCIENTIFIC R&D


Scientific discoveries are generally unpredictable. For example, Monsanto engineers found
some bacteria in the sludge outside their herbicide plant producing Round Up. This created
the curiosity to introduce the genetic traits of these bacteria in Round Up ready soybeans.
Such accidental discoveries are commonplace in scientific R&D. A variety of defense related
R&D expenditures, financed by government sources, gave rise to revolutionary breakthroughs
like the internet and biotechnology (especially the Human Genome Project). Public health
interests and, more recently, the emphasis on containing terrorist activities have been leading
128 Economics of Biotechnology

to increased government involvement in financing R&D. (Should the government organize


and coordinate these activities is a question that can be kept distinct from public funding of
such activities.)
The basic economic rationale for public research is the insufficient appropriability. That is,
certain activities are such that no one individual can claim ownership and/or recover the costs of
selling the resulting products on the market. For instance, scientific R&D production requires
finances (and other resources) and the results are conventionally available to everyone free of cost.
In most cases, and biotechnology appears to be an especially severe case, the investments are
large, the uncertainties are significant, and the time lags between the discovery and market returns
very large. Each of these aspects deters private firms to undertake R&D on any large scale.
Consider the following model to provide a brief overview of the process of R&D with
public funding as an alternative. Suppose a private firm targets a volume S of scientific
discoveries. Let S2/2δ represent the total investment in such R&D. In this formulation, δ is a
reflection of the R&D culture, motivation of the private investor, organizational competence,
and technical skill of the group. However, there is no assurance that the expectations will be
fulfilled. Suppose the actual result is S + u where u is a random variable with
E(u) = 0, and v(u) = σ2
(It is of course possible that the higher the S targeted the greater the variance. That is, v(u) may
be S2σ2 for instance.)
Assume that a unit value is associated with every unit of S. The net value to the private
investor is then given by
V = aS – S2/2δ – λS2σ2
where λS2 is the degree of risk aversion of the investor. It is expected that it increases with the
volume of investment. (The reader is invited to work out alternative formulations.) In this
formulation a represents the degree of appropriability of the returns of R&D from the viewpoint
of the private investor. It depends on the public good nature of the investments. (Some scientific
discoveries may be more valuable intrinsically. Then, it is possible to view a as a method of
capturing both of these aspects of R&D.)
Clearly, the investor will choose S to maximize V. This results in
S = aδ/(1 + 2λδσ2)
It can be readily verified that S increases as a and/or δ increases. However, it decreases
with an increase in λ. S = 0 in the extreme cases where a = 0, δ =0, or λ and σ2 are high. Pure
public goods, for which a = 0, will not be offered by the private firms. Similarly, a high degree
of risk inhibits private investments in R&D. These situations signal the need for the government
to finance such projects (or, at least, share some of the investment financing.)
It has been assumed so far that the net value is positive. However, situations of R&D in
the form of pure public goods are conceivable. In other words, the potential net value may
be negative if the entire R&D expenditure must be financed by the private firm. The
government may then step in and finance a fraction of the expenditure on R&D. See, for
example, Lawlor (2002).
Government Policy 129

Consider the case where the government finances a fraction f of S2/2δ. Under conditions
of partial appropriability the government may claim a share g of the value of the resulting
R&D. The choice of g can also be looked upon as a form of taxation. The net private value of
the investment can then be written as
Vp = private benefit
= (1–g)aS – (1–f)S2/2δ – λ(1–f)S2σ2, and
Vg = benefit to the government
= gS – fS2/2δ
P chooses S such that
S = (1–g)aδ/(1–f) (1 + 2λδσ2)
and the government chooses S given by
S = gδ/2f
It can therefore be inferred that in equilibrium
f/(1–f) = μ (some constant), and
g/(1–g) = 2μa/(1+2λδσ2)
Formulating the choice of optimal μ necessitates further assumptions. However, some
important results can be deduced from this exercise.
• When the risk is high the government can only claim a lower share of S in com-
parison to the investment that they make. In particular, g = 0 only if a = 0 or S2
is infinitely large
• In general, the government’s ability to recover costs will be low if a < 0.5
• Appropriability need not depend on the public good nature alone. Suppose the
gestation periods of converting scientific research to marketable product is long.
The time discounting, or the impatience of the private forms to recover their in-
vestments, makes a small
• Some scientific discoveries may not result in any marketable product contrary to
expectations
• If there are fixed costs of R&D there may be problems of recovery. Public funding
will then be necessary
As noted in chapter 4, the process of R&D and discovery is continuous over time. Hence,
a dynamic model may capture the effect of government spending more truthfully. The basic
model can be rewritten in the following form. Let the government expect the private NBF to
only finance a fraction f; 0 ≤ f ≤ 1 of the expenditure E. The optimization problem for the firm,
returning to the notation developed in chapter 4, will be

Max ∫ e–rt[Rα – fE]dt
0
130 Economics of Biotechnology

subject to
dR/dt = E – εR
It is straightforward algebra to show that the optimal R will now be
R = αV/f(r+ε)
That is, a smaller value of f surely results in larger R&D activity. Note, however, that if α is
kept high enough by IPR protection and f is also chosen to be low enough to achieve the same
socially optimal value of R there may be a volume of R&D far in excess of requirement. This
was noted in Phillips and Stovin (1999). Similarly, Byerlee and Fischer (2001) noted that
“complementarity with the private sector should be the central criterion in priority setting for
public research organizations. In the early stages, public sector support is often the key to
private sector entry into the market. However, once the private sector is established, the public
sector is often reluctant to withdraw, and in many cases becomes a competition. This may be
justified under certain conditions to maintain a competitive seed market in a situation of a
potential monopoly supplier, but in many cases, such as hybrid seeds, the public sector
continued to carry out such research well beyond justification.” On the other hand, a decrease
in f may also imply that a large part of R&D is such that its results cannot be appropriated by
private firms. That is, α may decrease. R may fall if α is sufficiently small. This was noted in
Cohen and Levin (1989). However, a formulation of the optimal f has been elusive primarily
because it is difficult to define the socially optimal R.
In general, taxation can be viewed as an effective policy measure to restore social welfare.
For, suppose the optimal R, that maximizes social welfare is
Rw = wαV
Suppose, now, that the government decides to tax a fraction g of value of the firm at each
point of time. Then, the firm

Max ∫ e–rt [(1–g)Rα – fE] dt
0
Subject to
dR/dt = E – εR
It can be readily verified that the optimal choice of R becomes
R = α(1–g)V/f(r + ε)
The government should then choose g such that
f/(1–g) = w, or
g = 1–f/w
For illustrative purposes, let f = 0.5, and w = 1.25. Then, it is obvious that g = 0.6. The tax rate
must be 60 percent if the share of public funding is 50 percent.
Government Policy 131

One qualification is in order. Suppose the government tries to balance its budget by
choosing

gV = (1–f)E
It is then obvious that
(1–g)V = Rα – (1–f)E
so that
(1–g)V – fE = Rα – E
so that the tax policy neutralizes the effect of government funding R&D.
Somewhat more general formulations are presented in Hall (2002) and Hall and VanReenen
(2000). These formulations tend to view such policies as affecting the user cost of capital. In
contrast, the static models indicate a more direct relationship between government policies
and the optimal choice of R&D.
Is government financing the only alternative? The following observations are pertinent.
• Patents and IPRs can improve appropriability even at the scientific level
• National health schemes, publicly supported health insurance policies, and agricul-
tural extension services have the effect of improving the marketability
• Public intervention may reduce the cost of obtaining finances. For instance, the cost
of internal finance increases infinitely if there are quantitative limits to its availabil-
ity. Venture capital, foreign direct investment and so on may augment supply and
thereby reduce the cost of financing.
Several other aspects of public intervention have been pointed out.
• Some low value projects, that are pertinent to disadvantaged groups, may not be
attractive to private firms. Public investment may then induce movement towards
better social value projects and this shift may not be related to appropriability per
se. The total value that can be generated itself becomes a consideration
• S may depend on some public knowledge and not merely expenditure on R&D.
In such a case, public knowledge, financed by the government, improves S
• Public funding, say on agricultural extension services, will improve the skills of
private farmers and allow them to utilize improved scientific knowledge. This
enables them to generate a greater S for a given ‘a’
Wolf and Zilberman (1999) and Lawlor (2000) considered issues of this nature.
Tax policies operate uniformly on all types of investment. On the other hand, as noted
above, the public interventions are specific to different needs. As such taxation is an inferior
choice. See, for example, Hall and van Reenan (2000). Lawlor (2000) also pointed out that the
undifferentiated nature of the operation of tax credits is such that even much applied and
developmental research, that can equally well attract sufficient private funding on its own,
may also end up being subsidized. This is also inefficient from a social point of view.
132 Economics of Biotechnology

One caveat is in order. Appropriability and/or risk is not a consideration when defense needσ
are involved. Such investments in R&D cannot be avoided. Public investment is inevitable in
such cases.
The above arguments carry over even in the context of bioprocessing and the relationship
between NBFs and large firms. The following points are noteworthy.
• ‘a’ may increase at the downstream level (closer to marketable product)
• Some risk at the scientific discovery stage is already resolved. This renders σ2 low
• However, there are chances of GM product being rejected at field trials or clinical
tests. This makes σ2 high
On an average, it can be expected that it increases much more than σ2. That is, the large firm
will accept a greater share of investment. Government intervention may not be important.
Should the government finance R&D or involve public institutions in doing R&D that can
be transferred to private firms eventually? Such open source concepts, even when initial
research is funded by private organizations, turned out to be a viable business model in the
context of information technology. It is also advocated in the context of some areas of
biotechnology. See, for instance, Rai (2005).

8.3 SCIENTIST VS. NBF CONTRACT


The relatively large sunk costs, uncertainty regarding the success of a biotechnology
discovery, and the appropriability of the expected gains have been significant obstacles in its
development. However, it is well known that there are substantial welfare gains from the
application of biotechnology.
When confronted with similar problems in other technological contexts governments
intervened to make the requisite investments before passing on the manufacturing
responsibilities to private firms. Financing scientific research in universities is one such activity.
That is, the scientist NBF network considered in the previous section has a prior network link
between the government and the university system. Almost invariably governments also found
that university research has its drawbacks in terms of the speed of delivery as well as the
proximity of university science to commercially exploitable ideas. In the context of agriculture
the requirements of extension services are too large for university scientists alone. Hence,
governments set up specialized research laboratories to accelerate commercialization. They
provide an intermediate network link between university scientists and NBFs at least on some
occasions. It is therefore worthwhile to examine this nexus in some analytical detail.
The classic justification for government financing of scientific activity is its appropriability.
Common examples are public health and bioremediation techniques used in the context of
environmental pollution. To fix ideas properly, assume that a specific scientific discovery has
the prospect of generating social welfare w though it is uncertain. In particular, let the actual
Government Policy 133

welfare gains be (w+u) where u is a random variable with


E(u) = expected value of u = 0, and
V(u) = variance of u = σ2 (a constant)
Assume that a university scientist, or a private research firm as the case may be, spends
some of its resources to achieve this breakthrough. Let w2/2δ represent these expenses where δ
= the level of skill. This cost may be looked upon as the opportunity cost of the scientist’s time to
himself and/or the organization to which he belongs. Suppose, to consider a fairly favorable
case, the society allows the scientist a share α of the welfare generated. Then, the net return of
the scientist is
πs = α(w + u) – w2/2δ
α may simply reflect the value he places on promotions, status, access to more research funds,
and so on. The scientist will be generally risk averse because the effort may not result in any
gains. As a result the net value of the discovery, to him, will be
Vs = αw – w2/2δ – λα2σ2, where
λ = his degree of risk aversion
He will choose
w = αδ
so as to maximize Vs. The net social welfare can be represented by
N = w – w2/2δ – λα2σ2
For all practical purposes, the welfare w is generated at a cost comprising of the scientist’s
time and his risk aversion since the society loses as a result of both. Taking the incentive
constraint of the scientist into account N becomes
N = αδ – α2δ/2 – λα2σ2
Since the relationship between the two parties under consideration is a cooperative enterprise
it will be expected that the choice of α will be such as to maximize N. Hence, the efficient α
will be
α = δ/(δ + 2λσ2)
Assume that the market valuation process results in this α and the corresponding
w = δ2/(δ + 2λσ2)
It can be easily verified that the cost incurred by the scientist = δ3/2(δ + 2λσ2)2, and expected
value of
πs = δ3/2(δ + 2λσ2)2
Let F be the sunk cost for the research worker. Whenever this is sufficiently large the net
expected gains may be inadequate to entice the scientist to proceed with the discovery. A
welfare increasing technology will not materialize.
Consider the possibility that the government agrees to pay a fraction β of the scientist’s
134 Economics of Biotechnology

variable cost or some portion of F. In the former case Eπs changes to


Eπs = δ3/ 2(1–β) [δ + 2(1–β)λσ2]2
which is higher for all values of β > 0. In other words, a suitable choice of β will ensure that the
potential social welfare materializes in practice.
The above argument implies that the large fixed costs of biotechnology research may be
the primary reason for government financing to ensure the realization of the potential social
welfare.
Filson and Morales (2005) offered an alternative explanation in a different, but related,
context. They consider a specific biotechnology activity, say a drug development, that is
expected to cost I. The project has only a probability p of success but not known apriori. Suppose
the project is successful. Then, the society is expected to derive welfare w from it. The expected
welfare is then pw and the net social welfare
N = pw – I
There is a possibility that pw < I. In such a case, a private biotechnology firm will not undertake
the project and the society does not get any welfare. The government, as stated above, has the
option of financing a part of I to make the project viable. Somewhat similar to the approach of
Filson and Morales (2005) consider an alternative. The government may initially invest an
amount e. This may enable the project to start and assess the probability p of success. The
private investor will invest (I–e) with probability p and nothing otherwise. The expected level
of investment is p(I–e). Similarly, the expected welfare is pw. Consequently, the net expected
benefit becomes
N = p[w – (I–e)] – e
= p(w–I) – e(1–p)
The private firm’s gain can be represented as
πp = p[w – (I–e)]
= (pw – I) + I(1–p) + pe
This quantity may be positive even if pw < I. To obtain an idea about the optimal e assume
that the private firm puts in an effort e2/2δ to enable it to discover the actual value of p. In
such a case
N = p[w –(I–e)] – e – e2/2δ
and the optimal e will be
e = (1–p)δ
This quantity increases with the expected skill level of the private firm. An alternative
formulation will be to assume that good projects are easy to identify while bad ones are not.
Hence, e will necessarily vary inversely with p. Let
e = c/p
where c is a constant.
Government Policy 135

It can be now shown that the optimal choice of e is


e = (I/c)1/2
This quantity varies directly with I but will be less than that amount. Hence, the government
spending, by assisting the firm in obtaining information about p, enables it to generate the
welfare expected from the project. Other alternatives, like the possible reduction in variance
that such expenditures entail, may be examined as well.
One important point should be addressed. How does the government administer the
subsidy that it is willing to offer? Clearly, this requires an organizational arrangement. The
general suggestion is that some government sponsored agency may be set up as a public
research laboratory where incubation and preliminary testing is carried out. Successful
discoveries may then be transferred to the private sector through appropriate networking
arrangements. However, such institutions experience information asymmetry and develop
their own internal bureaucracies and value systems that may be inimical to the development
of the biotechnology industry.
This page
intentionally left
blank
Chapter 9

CONCLUSION

9.1 THE TECHNOLOGY


Fundamentally the current developments in biotechnology pertain to the identification of the
biological processes through which plants and humans generate certain proteins. Once scientific
knowledge develops to a point where cell structures, cell functions, and biochemical reactions are
fully understood they have the prospect of replacing conventional chemical technologies that have
served the same purpose over the years. There are two fundamental advantages of this replacement.
• Erosion of the conventional resource base of chemical technologies need not be a
constraint on the development and production of proteins and so on. In fact, there
is a good prospect of biofuels replacing rapidly depleting fossil fuels. It is also
expected that there will be discoveries of many new materials. Developments in
nano technologies may turn out to be catalysts in this change.
• The current developments, of chemical based drugs and the fertilizer–pesticide
applications on crops, act on a global scale (the entire human body, the entire farm
area and so on) thereby reducing the effectiveness of the chemicals and creating
undesirable side effects (orally administered drugs affect the liver function, fertil-
izer and pesticide residues are found in food). Biotechnology operates at a more
micro level. As such the drugs and pesticides can be targeted to the exact location
of the human body and plants where they are needed. This reduces the cost of
application as well as minimizes the side effects.
From this vantage point biotechnology may be encouraged for purely scientific interest in the
short run. It should be acknowledged that biotechnology would be socially beneficial in the
long run. In other words, as of today, biotechnology should be developed as a backstop
technology that can be used when chemical based drugs and/or conventional plant breeding
is no longer feasible (i.e., their economic viability is surpassed).
138 Economics of Biotechnology

As of today a vast array of technologies are being developed and a large number of
biotechnology products will be available on the market in the foreseeable future.
One thing should, however, be clear. Biotechnology does not offer any miracles either in
the form of new methods of production, increased productivity, or reduced cost of production.
Traditional technologies cannot be completely replaced. In a similar vein it can be argued that
biotechnology does not as yet have the prospect of replicating the flexibility and biodiversity
achieved by conventional technologies. It is possible that this is purely due to the early stages
of biotechnology developments.

9.2 ORGANIZATIONAL ASPECTS


Four distinct aspects of commercialization of biotechnology have been recorded.
• Knowledge intensity
• Capital requirements
• High risks
• Concern about biodiversity and safety
All these features have a bearing on the type of organizational structures found in the industry.
Since the area of biotechnology is still new
• very few experts with specific knowledge are available
• private industry, even if it wants to attract them, find the supply too short
• the same is true of laboratory tools to scale up production
As a result some public sector involvement has been mandated. It consists of
• setting up educational and training programs
• setting up and sponsoring research
• transfer of knowledge to private firms
• tax holiday and other incentives to reduce financial risks
Two observations are pertinent.
• The nature of public organizations is such that they tend to attract a lot of political
patronage once they are established. As such it becomes difficult to dismantle them
at a later stage. The transitory public-private network relationships should change
so that public firms withdraw when they have outlived their utility
• Patents and IPRs granted to private firms may offer superior incentives as also
avoid the above problem
The nature and extent of government intervention is, at best, a pragmatic choice. Economic
theory does not offer adequate guidelines. However, as in the context of other technologies,
there will be long run government intervention in
• regulation
• pricing
• equitable distribution of gains
Conclusion 139

In other words, the steady state in biotechnology, once it is achieved, is not likely to be very
different from other industries.
With respect to conventional technologies knowledge diffusion and transfer of informal
knowledge is straight forward. The scientist develops the knowledge and technology, trains
young students in their use, private firms employ the students, and they in turn achieve efficient
transfer. This mechanism is not fully developed in the context of biotechnology. Hence, network
structures emerged as a pragmatic choice. In the long run private firms would have developed
adequate experience so that the networks tend to be internalized (as is the case of information
technology).
Note that in conventional technologies specialized jobs and stable job profiles emerged
over the years. However, the experiences are different in the context of the more recent
knowledge intensive technologies. For example, in the context of information technology, each
new production requires expertise of various kinds. Some of them are available within the
firm. Others must be acquired from outside. As such some form of networking and contract
jobs dominate. It appears that biotechnology is also heading in the same direction.
Financial resources available to a firm are insufficient in the initial years. As such venture
capital steps in to hedge the risk. However, over time private firms
• develop adequate resources of their own
• do not require the same amount of capital because investments will be marginal
in a steady state
That is, even financial arrangements will change towards a more conventional and predictable
structure over the long haul.
It can be concluded that even in the organizational context it is unlikely that there will be
any fundamental differences when compared to other technologies.
Consider the role of patents. The distinctive feature of biotechnology is patenting of
knowledge (that does not necessarily relate to a final product valued by consumers). In the
initial phases, when progress is slow and expensive, this may be necessary. There is already
awareness that this slows down the process of knowledge diffusion. In about 20–25 years it
can be expected that
• local entrepreneurs would have developed generic varieties of GM seeds that are
efficient in the agro climatic conditions of specific countries
• the TRIPS agreement would have lost much of its value since great many competing
technologies would have been developed.

9.3 PRODUCT PROFILES AND MARKETS


There is, by now, a general agreement that R&D and investments in biotechnology have
been rather expensive. It is also generally recognized that biotechnology does not have any
significant defense applications and as such public funding has been difficult to achieve. A
major share of activity is in the private sector. A few multinationals dominate the market.
140 Economics of Biotechnology

One of the consequences of this feature is that even when public funding is available private
firms accept control only so long as the R&D does not yield any profit. They want the
government to withdraw as soon as they can make profit. In other words, private firms want
public investment to be driven by their self interest rather than social welfare. Even developing
countries are coaxed into accepting government financed R&D which may result in products
of value to developed countries and profits for MNCs. Perhaps the developing countries can
afford to wait until they can obtain products suitable for their requirements. A second aspect
of biotechnology is that MNCs tend to concentrate on biotechnology products that are relatively
easy to discover. Seed production in the agricultural context is illustrative. Once a new product
is discovered the MNCs want even developing countries to use it (free trade comes as a handy
argument) even before the long term effects of their use can be ascertained. For, after all, this
is the only sure way of expanding their markets. The marketing strategies of the MNCs are
also questionable. First, they created a widespread speculation that conventional agriculture
as well as the green revolution have run their course. A quick conclusion has been drawn that
people in developing countries will starve if they do not accept biotechnology driven by the
MNCs. However, as yet traditional varieties appear to be superior and the apprehensions are
a false alarm meant to maximize the profits of private MNCs. Second, consider the following
kind of “scientific evidence” offered in Morse et al. (2005). They contend that seeds, produced
in India even by Monsanto, have a lower productivity compared to seeds of MNCs imported
from developed countries. On the face of it such attempts appear to be deliberate subversion
efforts of MNCs commercial interest.
Keeping competition out to establish monopoly power is very much an accepted
institutional practice. It is therefore not surprising that MNCs may be trying to destroy
traditional agriculture in developing countries by sending in harmful biotechnology products.
Unfortunately, the commercial greed of some individuals in developing countries may
contribute to this without any regard for social welfare.
It was also noted earlier that the MNCs are unwilling to set up production units in
developing countries even when it is less expensive to do so. As a result they are made to pay
higher prices. The monopoly power generated by patents has been misused.
It is rather early to speculate about the product profiles and price policies that will emerge
in a steady state.

9.4 NEGATIVE EFFECTS


The main point about biodiversity is that a large number of GM seeds, adapted to a vast
range of soil and climatic conditions are not available. In the absence of such variety
implementing biotechnology seeds in a hurry would result in
• lower productivity
• loss of traditional germplasm (which need to be stored on the field rather than in
seed banks) and possible destruction of varieties developed over the years after a
great deal of experimentation
Conclusion 141

The development of an equally large GM variety base is inhibited by


• one MNC or GM firm not having all the soil, climatic, and seed samples
• the high costs associated with modification of each variety relative to the small
localized demand
It is possible to overcome the first problem with adequate effort and at the cost needed to do
so. In a sense, the technological difficulty can be circumvented. The economic problem is more
difficult. It is perhaps possible to reduce costs with cumulative experience. The more difficult
question is that of who pays? If GM seeds are more expensive then traditional varieties (which
they will almost certainly) and if profits (if any) accrue to the MNCs the question of equity
will arise. However, the question will probably lose its relevance if over time it can be
demonstrated that the traditional varieties lost their productivity and GM gained to such a
point that only GM is economical. Similarly, there would be certain inevitability for the use of
GM even if it is not economical. This may also reduce protests. Either advances in technology
and/or economic compulsions may propel greater use of GM crops and products. Until then
issues of biodiversity will remain active.
The environmental issues are structurally the same as those raised in the context of the use
of fossil fuels or other chemical technologies. They are a result of the technology. However, they
can be circumvented, or minimized, either by technological modification and/or economic policy.
There are social costs of environmental degradation in the use of technology. This reduces social
welfare. However, both the technological and economic remedies to eliminate it are expensive.
As such the prices of the products of these technologies will increase. This may result in a decrease
in demand. The consequences for a reduction in social welfare are then obvious. Some balance
must be sought. Similarly, purely economic sanctions, given technology, may reduce economic
activity with attendant implications for social welfare. Once again it is necessary to look for a
compromise. The argument about the effects on future generations may not get the attention it
deserves so long as there is sufficiently rapid technological progress.
Detailed work on these aspects, as they relate to biotechnology, has not yet been
initiated in sufficient detail. In the final analysis efficient solutions may need to compromise
on biodiversity as well as biosafety for the sake of the welfare of the present generation
(for, extinction would only mean that there cannot be any future generations!) A more
optimistic view would be that the past two centuries have been such that the economic
problems- technology- economic policy cycles have been virtuous and resulted in overall
improvements in social welfare. Biotechnology revolution may yet be another phase in
this virtuous cycle.

9.5 STEADY STATE


In sum, the claim that the 21st century belongs to biotechnology the same way as physics
was the leader of the 20th century may well turn out to be correct. But this will fundamentally
change the way industrial activity is organized. The contours of this steady state are slowly
emerging.
This page
intentionally left
blank
Appendices
This page
intentionally left
blank
Appendix 1

TECHNICAL TERMS

Acquired Immunity—The cellular immune system causes, through simulation, immunity


towards a specific antigen.
Amino Acid—The fundamental building block of a protein molecule.
Antibodies—Protein molecules produced by B-cells. They are produced in response to the
presence of a specific antigen.
Antigen—A molecule (foreign substance) capable of activating B-cells and T-cells to induce
the formation of an antibody.
Assay—A method of determining the presence or quantity of a component.
B-Cell—A lymphocyte in the bone marrow that matures into an antibody secreting cell.
Bioremediation—A biotechnology to clean up environmental pollution created by chemical
technologies and hydrocarbon use.
Cell—The smallest structural unit of living organisms that is able to grow and reproduce
independently.
Clone—A group of cells with an identical genetic structure.
DNA—Nucleic acids are macromolecules formed from repeating units called nucleotides. A
nucleotide consists of a purine or pyrimidine base linked to a sugar phosphate. In
deoxyribonucleic acid (DNA) a purine (adenine A, or guanine G) or thymine/cytosine is linked
to deoxyribose sugar phosphate. In ribonucleic acid (RNA) a purine (A or G) or a pyrimidine
(uracil U or Cytosine C) is linked to a ribose sugar phosphate. Nucleotides are polymerized by
the reaction between the phosphate group of the nucleotide with the sugar of another to produce
a long polymer called polynucleotide. The DNA macromolecule in living cells is normally
present in the form of two nucleotide polymers closely associated with each other to form a
twisted spiral (double helix). The two strands in the double helix are held together by hydrogen
bonding between adjacent bases in the helix.
146 Economics of Biotechnology

DNA Hybridization—When the DNA molecule is exposed to near boiling temperatures, it


will unzip by breaking the bonds between base pairs. The DNA molecule will then change
from its double stranded normal state to two single strands. When complementary strands
are exposed to cooler temperatures they will bind together again. This process is called
hybridization.
ELISA Test—Several methods are available for determining the presence of genetic materials
in foodgrains, oil seeds, processed food, vaccines, and so on. ELISA is the protein based enzyme
linked immunosorbent assay technique. The ELISA test identifies a specific antibody reaction
that marks the presence of the new protein produced in GM crops. Dipstick tests are now
available to quantitatively detect biotech content in grain samples within two hours. Several
tests may be required to eliminate the presence of GM traits since the color coding
corresponding to each protein is different. However, it is more reliable and faster than PCR
based tests.
Enzyme—A protein that accelerates the rate of chemical reaction.
Genes—Elements of germplasm that transmit a hereditary character and forms a specific part
of a self-perpetuating DNA in the cell nucleus.
Gene Expression Technique—A method to identify the physical manifestation of the
information contained in a gene.
Gene Probes—The process of locating and analyzing those single genes that, if defective, can
cause a genetic disease. Diagnostic tests based on gene probes have been developed for cystic
fibrosis, sickle cell anemia, and so on.
Genome—The genome of a certain type of organism defines the comprehensive sequence of
nucleotide pairs constituting its DNA material. DNA can be arranged in a single circular
chromosome or in several linear chromosomes, each of which is segmented into informational
units referred to as genes. Each gene, in turn, contains within its DNA the specific instructions
to produce a protein, i.e., the actual coding of the protein sequence, and information about the
conditions of this expression. During the gene expression, different cellular elements come
together to produce that protein. This process occurs through an intermediate molecule called
messenger RNA (mRNA) whose sole purpose is to communicate by means of translation, the
information in the genetic code of the gene into the structural and functional elements that
specify that protein. Genomics is the study of an organism’s genome including the location,
structure, sequence, regulation, and functions of its genes.
In Situ—Within the human body.
In Vitro—Outside the human body.
MAb—Monoclonal Antibody—Cell fusion is the artificial joining of cells to form a new cell by
combining the desirable characteristics of two or more other cells. This technique produces
large quantities of monoclonal antibodies (MAbs).
Markers—Specific proteins to distinguish cancerous tumor cells to make the cancer a clear
target for the Mab therapeutics. Once a diagnostic antibody against a distinctive marker has
been made it can often be developed into a drug.
Appendix 1 Technical Terms 147

NIRS Test—Near infrared spectroscopy is the other tool that is faster and less expensive
compared to the ELISA test. It is based on the principle that the pattern of absorption or
reflection of NIRS light is unique for every compound. Thus the identification of the quantity
of materials like oil, proteins, and starches becomes relatively easy.
Polymerase Chain Reaction—PCR is a technique through which a particular DNA sequence
is reproduced exponentially. It involves the use of two DNA probes, that flank the ends of the
DNA of interest, adding the enzyme DNA polymerase and the four chemical bases constituting
the DNA.
Polypetide—A compound that yields amino acids on hydrolysis but has a lower molecular
weight than a protein.
Probes—Radioactive phosphorous introduced into one of the DNA strands to view the
hybridization process.
Promoters—Substances that can, in very small quantities, increase the activity of a catalyst.
Protein—A protein is composed of hundreds or thousands of amino acids.
Proteome—The study of the protein structure and activities present in the cell.
rDNA—Recombinant technology uses enzymes to cut and paste fragments of DNA to make
recombinant DNA molecules. Typically, a DNA sequence of interest, called the insert, is pasted
together with a vector, a piece of DNA that enables the recombinant molecule to be replicated
and harbored in a host organism. Recombinant molecules are constructed for the purpose of
cloning the DNA, i.e., making a large number of copies of a single molecule.
T-Cells—A type of lymphocyte originating in the bone marrow.
Vector—The agent used to carry new DNA into a cell. Viruses or plasmids are often used as
vectors.
This page
intentionally left
blank
Appendix 2

ECONOMIC CONCEPTS

A2.1 SPENCE FORMULA


The availability of a product generally results in some utility or value to the consumer.
The price he will pay per unit of output purchased on the market is a reflection of this value.
However, there are diminishing returns to value addition as the output increases. The market
is also generally such that the firm can charge only one uniform price from all its customers.
Hence, the market price is necessarily a reflection of the lowest value to the consumer of the
last unit of the product. Clearly, this means that the firm cannot fully convert the entire value
to the consumers into revenue for itself. For analytical purposes, it is useful to derive a
relationship between the value and sales revenue. This is the basic objective of the Spence
formula.
The theory of consumer demand generally indicates that the consumer’s optimal choice of
an output of a product is such that
∂U/∂Y = λp, where
U = utility or value
Y = volume of output
p = price per unit of Y
λ = marginal utility of a unit of money
For algebraic convenience it is generally postulated that the units of money are defined in
such a way that λ = 1. In such a case
p = ∂U/∂Y, and
150 Economics of Biotechnology

Y
U = ∫ p(y) dy
0

Of course, the integration is valid if and only if the demand curves satisfy the integrability
condition. However, any system of demand curves derived from a regular utility function
will satisfy the condition.
The purpose of analysis is to set up a relationship between U and the sales revenue
R = Yp(Y)
Consider the definition of the elasticity of demand, viz.,
η = – (dY/dp) (p/Y)
From this it follows that
p = – ηY (dp/dY)
Therefore, it can be inferred that
Y
U = ∫ p(y) dy
0

Y
= – ∫ ηY (dp/dY) dY
0

Y
= – η [Yp – ∫ p(y) dy]
0

Y
Hence, Yp(Y)η = – (1 – η) ∫ p(y) dy
0

Therefore, the relationship being sought is


Y
Yp(Y) = (1 – 1/η) ∫ p(y) dy
0

This is the Spence formula. Since η > 1 in the operationally relevant range it can be verified
that the revenue is almost always less than the total value generated. They will be equal only
in competitive markets.

A2.2 ECONOMIES OF SCALE AND SCOPE


Following Chandler (1990) economies of scale may be defined as “those that result when
increased size of a single operating unit producing or distributing a single product reduces the
unit cost of production or distribution.” In practice, the size of a firm has been measured by
Appendix 2 Economic Concepts 151

• the capacity of the firm (in terms of the potential maximum output, the stock of
capital, or many other fixed or sunk costs), or
• actual output produced
Consider the short run total cost curve of a firm. It depends on the
• stock of capital (fixed in the short run)
• actual level of production
• prices of various factors of production
It may be written as
C = aKα + bYβ ; α,β < 1, where
C = total cost of production
K = potential output or stock of capital
Y = actual level of production
In general, if the fixed cost is written as
F = aKα
a part of the economies of scale arise from spreading F over a wider range of output. For, the
average fixed cost F/Y decreases with an increase in Y. However, as the above formulation
suggests, F may itself not increase proportionately with the capacity level of output. This is
also an aspect of economies of scale. From this vantage point the fixed costs (generally called
the sunk costs because such assets do not have any value outside the activity for which they
are designed) are the major source of economies of scale. Drug discovery, drug development
(i.e., clinical tests of drugs), and field trials of crops and such R&D activities should be
considered as sources of economies of scale. See, for example, Cockburn and Henderson (2001)
and Fulton and Giannakis (2001). The other component of the short run cost is the variable
cost depending on the level of output. Efficient use of the variable factors of production will
be at the apex of such economies of scale.
Chandler (1990) expressed these differences in the following way.
• “In the older, labor intensive industries, increases in the output of a manufacturing
firm came primarily by adding more machines and more workers to operate them.
In the newer industries, expanded output came from a drastic change in the capital-
labor ratios. It came by improving and rearranging inputs; by using new or greatly
improved machinery, furnaces, and other equipment; by reorienting the processes
of production within the plant; by placing several intermediary processes employed
in making a final product within a single firm; and by increasing the application
of energy.”
• “The potential cost advantages could not be fully realized unless a constant flow
of materials through the firm was maintained to ensure effective capacity utiliza-
tion. The sunk costs are much higher. Thus, the two decisive figures in determining
152 Economics of Biotechnology

costs were rated capacity and throughput (the actual amount of output). The through-
put needed to maintain minimum efficient scale requires careful coordination not
only of the flow through the process of production but also of inputs from suppliers
and the flow of output to intermediaries and users.”
The following aspects are significant while explaining the economies of scale emanating
from the fixed cost component.
• Consider the production process that consists of using a cylindrical pipe to trans-
port some liquid. The cost of construction of the pipe (of a fixed length) depends
on the radius and the surface area. On the other hand, the capacity increases with
volume (or the square of the radius). Hence, the cost per unit of transporting the
capacity level of output decreases with the volume.
• At any given time, industrial equipment is available only in fixed sizes and capaci-
ties. There are increasing returns, for every given size of equipment, upto the
capacity level of operation because this enables the firm to spread the fixed costs.
• An increase in size may also lead to economies in maintenance staff. For, the law
of large numbers suggests that breakdowns are more predictable. Consequently,
maintenance staff need not increase proportionately with size.
• Drug development (in addition to research on discovery) may experience increas-
ing returns to scale. For, undertaking an activity on a larger scale permits the
adoption of more efficient techniques.
• Firms generally incur substantial expenditures in clinical trials of drugs and field
trials of crops and for obtaining regulatory approval. When the firm increases its
level of production these costs need not be incurred all over again. This is valid
though the production of additional units of output will require additional cost.
Large firms will derive economies of scale by spreading regulatory costs over more
output. This aspect was noted in Fulton and Giannakis (2001) and Cockburn and
Henderson (2001).
Consider the economies of scale in the variable factors. The following arguments are
pertinent.
• Assume that a product must be processed on two machines. Then, the production
process consists of five elementary operations, viz., giving input to machine 1,
processing on machine 1, transferring the inprocess material to machine 2, process-
ing on machine 2, and storing the final output. There will be some idle time on both
the machines if one person handles all the steps. Further, his skills may not be best
suited to operate both the machines either. Hence, the marginal product will be
small initially. However, if the number of workers increases steadily towards five
each of the operations can be carried out independently (and everybody can be a
specialist in a particular task). There is a gain in efficiency due to the repetition of
a single task as well as a reduction in the idle time. Hence, it will be expected that
the marginal product will increase steadily until five workers are employed. This
suggests that the average costs of production decrease as output increases.
Appendix 2 Economic Concepts 153

• Large firms may have advantages in the financial markets over smaller firms. In
particular, large firms may be in a position to finance their working capital require-
ments through bank credit obtained at lower interest rates. (For, the banks can save
on transaction costs by handling a few large accounts.)
In sum, economies of scale can be expected due to
• economies of increased physical dimensions of plant
• existence of indivisibilities
• specialization and division of labor
• economies (due to transaction costs) of massed resources
By way of contrast, economies of scope are those resulting from the use of processes within
a single operating unit while producing or distributing more than one product. More formally,
suppose
C(Y1,Y2) < C(Y1,0) + C(0,Y2)
In other words, the cost of producing Y1, Y2 together is less than that of producing them
separately. The production process is then said to exhibit economies of scope. In practice, the
following kinds of economies of scope can be identified.
• When the firm has excess capacity and the market for its primary product is
saturated it will try to expand into related products. If technology is malleable and
accommodates the production of another product without disrupting the produc-
tion of the main product then there will be an efficient use of capital assets.
• Some factors of production are public (non-rival) in the sense that once they have
been acquired for use in producing one product, they are costlessly available for
production of another. R&D expenditures are a good example especially when
inventions are cumulative. Suppose a biotechnology firm isolated a particular gene.
The firm can use this to expand its activities. For example, if the firm desires to
develop seeds for a new crop, it need not invest in the R&D once again.
• Competence in the production of one product line may create competence to pro-
duce another related product. This is also a sunk cost explanation of economies of
scope.
• Some production processes exhibit cost complementarities. That is, the marginal
cost of producing one product falls as the output of the other increases. For ex-
ample, if one chemical is made from a byproduct of another, then increased pro-
duction of the latter may reduce the marginal cost of the former.
Economies of scope in demand have also been noted. As Just and Heuth (1993) argued,
scope economies in demand can be said to materialize if the firm can generate greater net
profits by marketing two or more products together. In the pharmaceutical market certain
chemical and biotechnology related products complement each other. This is especially valid
in the context of diagnostic kits and drug cocktails for the treatment of AIDS. The other major
source is the nature of physician prescriptions, public health schemes, and promotional activities
of large firms. The chemical and seed firms in agricultural biotechnology area derive advantages
154 Economics of Biotechnology

from tie-in sales of biotechnology related seeds and chemical supplements. In the early stages
of biotechnology innovation small firms, operating in niche segments, dominated the market.
However, with subsequent developments it has become profitable for large firms to diversify
so that they can take advantage of the economies of scope in demand.
Network effects are also often a case of economies of scope. For, in industries like
biotechnology, communications, cyberspace, and so on a larger network of relationships
between firms and related products enables the firm to develop faster and at a lower cost.

A2.3 VALUATION OF RISKY ASSETS


Consider the valuation of the common stock of a firm by a shareholder. Let the investor
have one unit of money at his disposal. One possible investment is a bank deposit. This provides
him a fixed return on his investment. Let this be written as qf. Investing in the stock market is
another alternative. Suppose the investor opts for a diversified portfolio with the weightage
generally assigned in the stock exchange price index. The basic motivation for this choice is of
course the attempt to reduce the risk by holding a diversified portfolio. Suppose the stock
price index is qm. This is random. It may also be difficult to assign any probability to different
values that it takes. The third alternative is to choose the common stock of one of the companies
instead of the diversified portfolio. Suppose the share price is q. Clearly, this price q is random.
It is likely to be more volatile than qm and perhaps much less predictable. Suppose the investor
decided to buy this specific stock. Then, conceptually, for some value of β he is considering
the investment in the specific risky asset to be equivalent to putting a fraction β of his money
in qm and the rest in qf. This is the spirit of the Von Neumann approach to the valuation of the
common stock of a specific firm. That is,
β of qm
q
(1 – β) of qf
Or, more explicitly, write
q = βqm + (1 – β)qf
Hence, based on the expected value calculation,
E(q) = β E(qm) + ( 1 – β) qf
The prospective shareholder must reveal this choice of β.
An attempt can now be made to provide an analytical approach to identify the value of β.
Consider the more general portfolio
γ of q
p (1 – γ)β of qm
(1 – γ) (1 – β) of qf
Appendix 2 Economic Concepts 155

That is, let the investor put a fraction γ of his saving in the specific common stock, a
fraction (1 – γ)β in the diversified portfolio, and the rest in the risk free investment. Then,
the return from the general portfolio can be written as
p = γq + (1 – γ)βqm + (1 – γ) (1 – β)qf
The expected value of the generalized portfolio is given by
E(p) = γ E(q) + (1 – γ) [β E(qm)+ (1 – β) qf]
= γE(q) + (1 – γ)E(q)
= E(q)
That is, the shareholder considers these two alternatives to be equivalent in expected value
terms for all values of γ. It can then be surmised that he chooses γ to minimize the variance if
he is risk averse. The variance of p is given by
V(p) = γ2 V(q) + (1 – γ)2 β2 V(qm) + 2γ (1 – γ) β Cov (q, qm)
Hence, the optimal value of γ can be readily computed. It should now be noted that the portfolio
p is reduced to q if and only if the optimal choice of γ = 0. In other words, while valuing the
common stock of the company the shareholder can be expected to reveal
β = Cov (q,qm) / V(qm)
From this it follows that the price he is willing to pay for a unit of common stock of this
company can be written as
q = β* qm + (1 – β*) qf
= constant + β* qm
For all practical purposes this CAPM (capital asset pricing model) valuation of the common
stock is the incentive constraint of the shareholder. It articulates the preference of the
shareholder in relation to the overall market price of stocks and shares.

A2.4 TRANSFER PRICING REGULATION


Strategic transfer pricing may have several negative effects. A few prominent issues can
be highlighted. First, a foreign company may charge a lower price (in contrast to what domestic
firms can offer) mainly because the market demand is elastic. It is possible even when they do
not have any cost advantage. The consumers may find this advantageous. But the domestic
industry may suffer. It may then be necessary to check such pricing. Second, just the opposite
may also happen. For instance, a foreign pharmaceutical firm may deny selling life saving
drugs except at a high price simply because patents provide it such protection. In other words,
low cost production, even when it is possible, may not be allowed. Instead, high production
costs will be cited as a justification for charging higher prices. Third, the firm may take
advantage of lower tax rates to derive greater than normal profits. This may apply to income
taxes in the context of services, profit taxes and excise taxes, and sales taxes in the case of
commodities and so on. The basic effects of these distortions may be (a) changing the
distribution of gains between the contracting parties without altering efficiency (as in the case
156 Economics of Biotechnology

of price discrimination), (b) affect efficiency (especially when motivational problems arise), or
(c) impinge on third parties outside the contractual relationship. There is resistance to regulation
in the first case. However, arms-length transfer pricing regulations are put in place in the
other two contexts.
Three basic alternatives have been proposed; comparable uncontrolled price (CUP method)
or a resale price method, cost plus method (CPM), and profit split method (PSM). The rationality
behind these methods is as follows.
CUP method – Pricing of any product or service is based on the cost of production. Every
firm should be expected to use a cost comparable to the nearest rival or the cost of producing
output within the country if foreign competition is involved. Brazil argued with Cipla on
these grounds with respect to the manufacture of drugs for AIDS. A similar situation arose in
the context of producing statins for cardiological uses.
CPM method – There can be differences in the markup used for pricing even when the
costs are comparable. The stipulation is therefore the comparison with the percentage markup
by the nearest rival product.
PSM method – An alternative to comparing markup will be to examine profit rates and
rates of return on capital. In particular, it is generally agreed that gross profit to operating cost
should be comparable.
Putting the conceptual and operating details aside it should be recognized that there can
be misuse of transfer pricing when there is information uncertainty. Some contracts, based on
transfer pricing, need more elaborate control.
Appendix 3 Mathematical Background 157

Appendix 3

MATHEMATICAL BACKGROUND

A3.1 CONSTRAINED OPTIMIZATION

Consider the problem of using a scarce resource for the production of a product. Assume that
x units of the resource produces an output
Y = f(x)
The firm, that uses resource x to produce y can obtain a value
v = g(x)
in this process of production and sale. v need not always be the profit generated.
Suppose the firm owns the resource and R units of it are available. The problem for
the firm is to choose x to maximize v subject to x ≤ R. Referring to Fig. A.1 two situations
are conceptually possible; R may be Rl or Rr. That is, the free maximum of v is not possible
g(x)

O
Ri X m Rr X
Fig. A.1
158 Economics of Biotechnology

if R= Rl or the resource R will not be fully utilized if R = Rr. In the first case, the last unit of the
resource used in the production of y adds something positive to the value v. In the second
case, some units of resource are redundant in the context of increasing the value v. Some units
of the resource R are then of zero value to the firm.
A general solution to the problem may now be outlined. Define the Hamiltonian
H = g(x) + λ (R – x)
In this formulation, H is the total value of the resource to the firm. g(x) is the value from
transforming x units of the resource to output y. (R – x), the rest of the resources may also have
the potential of increasing y and adding to v. Therefore, λ can be looked upon as the marginal
value of a unit of the resource. λ is usually designated as the Lagrange multiplier. However,
this economic interpretation is very useful in appreciating the logic behind the method of
solution. Clearly, the firm wants to maximize H.
Suppose, now, that R is fully utilized to produce y. Then, R = x. In fact, when R = Rl, an
additional unit of the resource still has a positive value. Then, λ > 0. It is possible, on the
other hand, that Rr of the resource is available. Then (R – x) > 0 and the available resource
will not be fully utilized. That is, additional units of the resource, beyond xm, will not add to
the value of the firm. Consequently, it can be inferred that λ = 0. A formal statement will
now be that
λ > 0 if R < xm
= 0 if R > xm
This is the well-known Kuhn Tucker condition.
To obtain the efficient value of x, to solve the constrained maximization problem,
consider the free maximum of g(x). Suppose x*, the free maximum, is less than the available
R. Then, there is a surplus of resources and the constraint is redundant. Nothing better
than x* can be chosen. Suppose, on the other hand, that x* > R. Then, x * cannot be attained.
Only a constrained maximum is possible. The x* for the constrained maximization problem
is equal to R.

A3.2 DYNAMIC OPTIMIZATION


Consider the following problem. Suppose a firm has an initial stock of capital x0 at time t0.
Assume that it estimated the likely demand for its products at t1 > t0 and decided that it will
need a stock of capital x1 to cater to the expected market demand. The firm wants to know the
best route through which it can augment x0 to x1. The accompanying Fig. A.2 suggests three
possible approaches to investment. In general, there is infinite choice.
Appendix 3 Mathematical Background 159

x1 B

A
x0

O
t0 t1 t
Fig. A.2
How will the firm be affected if it chooses one path instead of the other? Suppose, the firm
increases x0 to x1 at t0. It incurs a cost. However, the production capacity cannot be fully utilized
until t1. That is, the investment cannot be recovered efficiently. Suppose, instead, that it
postpones the entire investment until time t1. This saves costs but the firm loses revenue for t
≤ t ≤ t1 because it cannot increase production commensurate with the expected changes in
demand. Hence, there is some optimal x(t) for each t between t0 and t1. Further, the optimal
choice depends on the value generated over the time horizon.
Let v represent the value at t. Clearly, it depends on x as well as dx/dt. For, investments in
excess of or short of requirements dictated by an increase in demand do not add value. The
problem for the firm is to choose x(t) so as to
t1
Max ∫ v(x, dx/dt) dt
t0

subject to
x(t0) = x0, and x(t1) = x1
Clearly, v explicitly depends on the information about market demand and the cost of
production. This is the classic two point boundary value problem in calculus of variations.
A solution to this problem can be developed by using simple calculus. Assume that x(t) is
the optimal trajectory and x*(t) = x(t) + dx(t) is any neighboring trajectory. Of course, this
should also satisfy the boundary conditions. That is,
x*(t0) = x0 = x(t0) + dx(t0)
= x0 + dx(t0)
Hence, dx(t0) = 0. Similarly, dx(t1) = 0. Consider
v = v[x*, dx*/dt] = v[x+dx, dx/dt + d2x/dt2]
Expanding the right hand side using first order Taylor’s series yields
v = v(x,dx/dt) + (dv/dx) dx + [dv/d(dx/dt)] (dx/dt)
160 Economics of Biotechnology

Therefore, it can be inferred that


t1 t1 t1 t1
∫ v* dt = ∫ v dt + ∫(∂v/∂x) dx + ∫[∂v/∂(dx/dt)] d(dx/dt)
t0 t0= t0 t0

Consider
∫ [∂v/∂(dx/dt)] d(dx/dt) dt = [∂v/∂(dx/dt)] (dx/dt)
– ∫ {d[∂v/∂(dx/dt)]/dt] (dx/dt)
Since dx/dt = 0 at t0 as well as t1 it follows that
t1 t1 t1
∫ v dt = ∫ v dt + ∫ [(∂v/∂x) – d{∂v/∂(dx/dt)}/dt] (dx/dt) dt
*

t0 t0 t0
Therefore, the derivative of
t1
∫ v(x, dx/dt) dt
t0

with respect to x(t) will be zero if


d{∂v/∂(dx/dt)}/dt = ∂v/∂x
This is usually designated as the Euler condition for optimization.
By way of an example consider the problem
t
Max ∫ {xα – [(dx/dt) + εx]} dt
0

subject to
x0 = 0, and x1 = x*
For this problem
v [x,dx/dt] = xα – [(dx/dt) + εx]
∂v/∂x = αxα–1 – ε
∂v/∂(dx/dt) = – 1
Therefore, the optimal x is such that
αxα-1 – ε = 0, or
x = (ε/α)1/(α–1)
A more general problem can now be formulated. Consider
t1
Max ∫ v(x,u) dt
t0
Appendix 3 Mathematical Background 161

subject to
dx/dt = f(x,u)
where u is the choice of the firm. It is usually designated as a control. This problem can be
solved by using the Lagrange multiplier method. Define
H(x, dx/dt, u) = v(x,u) + λ [f(x,u) – dx/dt]
Clearly, the maximization problem is equivalent to
t1
Max ∫ H(x, dx/dt, u) dt
t0

The Euler condition may now be utilized to solve the problem. Note that in the modified
specification both x and u can be treated as independent choices. Further,
∂H/∂(du/dt) = 0
since H is independent of du/dt.
Similarly,
∂H/∂(dx/dt) = – λ
Hence, the two Euler conditions for the optimization problem are
dλ/dt = – ∂H/∂x, and
∂H/∂u = 0
This is the Pontryagin’s maximum principle in its essential detail. Inequality constraints
can be handled by suitable Lagrange multiplier techniques and Kuhn-Tucker conditions.
Consider the following example.
T
Max ∫ (xα – E) dt
0

subject to
dx/dt = E – εx
Construct the Hamiltonian
H = xα – E + λ(E – εx)
Then, by Pontryagin’s maximum principle,
dλ/dt = – ∂H/∂x
= – αxα–1 + λε
and since H contains the expression – E (1–λ) linearly, the optimal E must be such that λ = 1
since an optimal E > 0 is sought. It now follows that
αxα–1 = ε, or
x = (ε/α)1/(α–1)
and the corresponding E will constitute the optimal solution.
162 Economics of Biotechnology

Note, incidentally, that this example is the same as the previous one. But Pontryagin’s
maximum principle is far more general.

A3.3 NASH EQUILIBRIUM


Almost all economic problems deal with exchange between two or more individuals.
Invariably, each party makes an attempt to pursue maximization of its own goal. Economic
theory posits that the market, as an organizational mechanism, arbitrates between these
divergent interests and brings about an equilibrium in which maximum gains to a maximum
number of individuals can be achieved. In practice, the bargaining process is not impersonal
because only a finite number of individuals are involved in the exchange. Economic theory
needs to grapple with a way of describing their strategic interaction and characterizing an
efficient equilibrium. Efficient terms of contract or bargain must be specified to proceed with
economic analysis. Nash equilibrium is one such concept.
Consider the following. Suppose two individuals, say X and Y, are involved in the bargain.
Let x and y be their respective choices. By the nature of the problem both of them recognize
that though they wish to maximize their personal gains, what they can achieve depends on
the choice of the other. This can be characterized by writing their respective gains as π1 (x,y)
and π2 (x,y). Clearly, while choosing x the individual X must either know y or assume it to be
parametric to begin with. That is, conceptualize X maximizing π1 for a given y in his choice of
x. This results in
x = f(y)
Economic theory characterizes this as the reaction function of X or as his participation constraint.
In a similar fashion, the choice of Y can be written as
y = g(x)
where g is not necessarily f even if it exists. Clearly, the choice (x*,y*) that satisfies both these
–1

participatory constraints is such that neither of them can do any better for the optimal choice
of the other. For, exchange cannot take place unless both of them consent. Such a (x*,y*) is
called a Nash equilibrium if it exists.
Consider the following simple numerical example to illustrate the usefulness of this concept
and its implications. Let X produce an input x that Y requires to produce an output y. Assume
that the production function is
X = y2
X incurs a cost
C = x2
to produce the input. Postulate, for simplicity, that Y sells output in the market at a price p per
unit. The bargain is essentially for a price q at which X offers a unit of x to Y. The profit
function of X can be represented by
πx = qx – x2
Appendix 3 Mathematical Background 163

Hence, he will demand a price q such that


q = 2x
This is the incentive constraint of X. Similarly, the profit for Y is
πy = py – qy2
Hence, Y would be willing to offer a q such that
p = 2qy
This represents the incentive constraint of Y. The Nash equilibrium value of q is such that
q = 2x = 2y2
= p/2y
Hence, p = 4y3; or, y = (p/4)1/3
Consequently, the choice of q is
q = 2 (p/4)2/3
Observe that the total profit, or value, generated by the transaction is the sum of the profits
of both X and Y. That is,
N = net value of the contract
= py – x2
= py – y4
The value of y that maximizes N is such that
p = 4y3, or
y = (p/4)1/3
This is the Nash equilibrium value.
Stated briefly, whenever a unique Nash equilibrium exists, it maximizes the net value of
the exchange.

A3.4 PRINCIPAL AGENT PROBLEM


Economic theory acknowledges that due to strategic reasons X and Y may not reveal their
reactions truthfully. It would also be expensive for the other party to obtain this information
accurately if they try to do so on their own. As a result, there is always a certain degree of
uncertainty in approaching these equilibrium concepts. Fundamentally, uncertainty may be
external to the parties in exchange or it may be intrinsic due to their patterns of behavior.
Therefore, a modification of the Nash equilibrium concept is sought.
The most popular is that of Kawasaki and McMillan (1987). Assume that a principal Y
commissions the production of x through an agent X. Let the agreement be that X will produce
x at a cost x2/2δ where δ is a characterization of his efficiency. However, in the execution of the
contract, X may find it impossible to deliver x at a cost x2/2δ due to reasons beyond his control
164 Economics of Biotechnology

(environmental uncertainty) or, he may not be motivated to deliver all of x (usually this is
designated as reneging or moral hazard). Let the output delivered be x+u where u is a random
variable with
E(u) = expected value of u = 0
V(u) = variance of u = σ2
Normally, in such contracts the principal agrees to pay the agent a fraction f of the revenue
from the sale of x. Then, the profit for X is
πx = f(x+u) – x2/2δ
assuming that the market price of x is unity. The KM formulation postulates that X will be risk
averse. The value of πx to him will then be
Vx = fx – x2/2δ – λf2σ2
where λ > 0 represents his degree of risk aversion. Given a f, he agrees to offer x such that
x = fδ
KM now postulates that Y chooses f so as to maximize the net value of the contract. Note that
the gain to Y can be written as
πy = (1–f) (x+u)
However, in general, the principal is risk neutral since he has many other avenues of
diversifying his risk. Hence, he maximizes the net value of the contract
N = x – x2/2δ – λf2σ2
subject to the participatory constraint of X, namely,
x = fδ
Write N in the form
N = fδ – f2δ/2 – λf2σ2
The f that maximizes N is the efficient solution in the KM model. That is,
f = δ/(δ+2λσ2)
It is an increasing function of δ and a decreasing function of λ.
Note that the Nash equilibrium characterization does not adequately take risk aversion
into account. However, from a practical viewpoint, it is difficult to assert a priori that one of
these concepts is superior to the other. Empirical evidence has not been conclusive either.
References 165

REFERENCES

Abrol, D. (2005), The Question of Patentability of Biotechnological Subject Matter: Issues and
Options Before the Policy Makers, Asian Biotechnology and Development Review, 7,
53-73.
Alexander, M.T., O. Furrer, and D. Sudharshan (2003), A Hierarchical Framework of New
Products Development: An Example from Biotechnology, European Journal of
Innovation Management, 6, 48–63.
Alfranca, O., and W.E. Huffman (2003), Aggregate Private R&D Investments in Agriculture:
The Role of Incentives, Public Policies, and Institutions, Economic Development and
Cultural Change, 51, 1–21.
Allen, F., and D. Gale (1999), Diversity of Opinion and Financing of New Technologies,
Journal of Financial Intermediation, 8, 68-89.
Alston, J.M., and R.J. Venner (2002), The Effects of the US Plant Variety Protection Act on
Wheat Generic Improvement, Research Policy, 31, 527-542.
Alteiri, M.A., and P. Rosset (1999), Ten Reasons Why Biotechnology Will Not Ensure Food
Security, Protect the Environment and Reduce Poverty in the Developing World,
AgBioForum, 2, 155-162.
Anderson, K., L.A. Jackson, and C.P. Nielsen (2004), Genetically Modified Rice Adoption:
Implications for Welfare and Poverty Alleviation, World Bank Policy Research Working
Paper, WPS 3380.
Argyres, N.S., and J.P. Leibeskind (2000), Governance Inseparability and the Evolution of the
U.S. Biotechnology Industry, Presented at the 2001 ISNIE Conference, Berkeley.
Arora, A. (1994), Evaluating Technological Information and Utilizing It, Journal of Economic
Behavior and Organization, 24, 91-114.
Arora, A. (1996), Contracting for Tacit Knowledge: The Provision of Technical Services in
Technology Licensing Contracts, Journal of Development Studies, 50, 223-256.
166 Economics of Biotechnology

Arora, A., and A. Fosfuri (2003), Licensing the Markets for Technology, Journal of Economic
Behavior and Organization, 52, 277-295.
Arora, A., and A. Gambardella (1990), Complementarity and External Linkages: The Strategies
of the Large Firms in Biotechnology, Journal of Industrial Economics, 38, 361-379.
Audretsch, D.B., and P.E. Stephan (1996), Company-Scientist Locational Links: The Case of
Biotechnology, American Economic Review, 86, 641-652.
Austin, D.H. (1993), An Event Study Approach to Measuring Innovative Output: The Case
of Biotechnology, American Economic Review, 83, 253-258.
Austin, D.H. (2000), Patents, Spillovers, and Competition in Biotechnology, Resources for the
Future.
Avramovic, M. (1996), An Affordable Development? Biotechnology, Economics, and the
Implications for the Third World (London: Zed Books).
Balasubramanian, D., C.E.A. Bryce, K. Dharmalingam, J. Green, and K. Jayaraman (2004),
Concepts in Biotechnology (Hyderabad: Universities Press).
Barham, B.L., D. Jackson-Smith, and S. Moon (2000), The Adoption of rBST on Wisconsin
Dairy Farms, AgBioForum, 3, 181-187.
Barham, B.L., J.D. Foltz, D. Jackson-Smith, and S. Moon (2004), The Dynamics of Agricultural
Biotechnology Adoption: Lessons From rBST Use in Wisconsin 1994-2001, American
Journal of Agricultural Economics, 86, 61-72.
Benett, R.M., Y. Ismael, U. Kambhampati, and S. Morse (2004), Economic Impact of Genetically
Modified Cotton in India, AgBioForum, 7, 96-100.
Berglund, D., and M. Clarke (2000), Using Research and Development to Grow State
Economies, available at www.nga.org/eda/files/2000RESEARCH.pdf
Betemps, S., and G.Venuprasad (2004), Contributing to Improved Health Care Through
Promotion of Regional Trade Expansion, India Trade Center.
Bhattacharya, J., and W.B. Vogt (2003), A Simple model of Pharmaceutical Price Dynamics,
Journal of Law and Economics, 46, 599-626.
Bhattacharya, S., and S. Guriev (2004), Knowledge Disclosure, Patents, and Optimal
Organization of Research and Development, Discussion Paper No. TE/04/478, London
School of Economics and Political Science.
Bottazzi, G., G. Dosi, M. Lippi, F. Pammolli, and M. Riccaboni (2001), Innovation and Corporate
Growth in the Evolution of the Drug Industry, International Journal of Industrial
Organization, 19, 1161-1187.
Brown. L., A. Walker, A.M. Walters, A. Harding, and L. Thurecht (2002), Funding of High
Cost Biotechnology and Other Innovative Targeted Therapies Under the
Pharmaceutical Benefit Scheme, University of Canberra.
Chandler, A.D. (1990), Scale and Scope: The Dynamics of Industrial Capitalism (Cambridge:
Harvard University Press).
References 167

Chattopadhyay, A., and T.M. Horbulyk (2004), Strategic Public Policy Towards Agricultural
Biotechnology with Externalities in Developing Countries, Journal of Agricultural &
Food Industrial Organization, 2, Article 6.
Chaturvedi, S. (2002), Agricultural Biotechnology and New Trends in IPR Regime, Economic
and Political Weekly, March 30, 1212-1222.
Chaturvedi, S., and S.R. Rao (2004), Biotechnology and Development (New Delhi: Academic
Foundation).
Chaudhuri, S. (2004), The Pharamaceutical Industry, in S. Gokarn, A. Sen, and R.R. Vaidya
(eds.) The Structure of Indian Industry (New Delhi: Oxford University Press).
Chaudhuri, S., P.K. Goldberg, and P. Jia (2003), Estimating the Effects of Global Patent
Protection in Pharmaceuticals: A Case of Qunolenes in India, Unpublished Manuscript.
Chern, W.S., K. Rickertson, N. Tsboi, and T. Fu (2003), Consumer Acceptance and Willingness
to Pay for Genetically Modified Vegetable Oil and Salmon: A Multiple Country
Assessment, AgBioForum, 5, 105-122.
Chung, C., and J.E. Pettigrew (1998), Economics of Soybean Biotechnology in the Livestock
Industry, International Food and Agribusiness Management Review, 1, 373-385.
Cockburn, I., and R.M. Henderson (2001), Scale and Scope in Drug Development: Unpacking
the Advantages of Size in Pharmaceutical Research, Journal of Health Economics, 20,
1033-1057.
Cohen, W., and R. Levin (1989), Innovation and Market Structure, in R. Schmalensee and R.D.
Willig (eds.) Handbook of Industrial Organization (Amsterdam: Elsevier Science
Publishers).
Collins, W., and M. Petit (1998), Strategic Issues for National Policy Decisions in Managing
Genetic Resources, World Bank Special Report 23926.
Correa, C. (2001), Patents, TRIPS, and R&D Incentives: A Southern Perspective, available
at www. cmhealth. org/docs/wg2_paper12. pdf
Correa, C. M. (2005), The TRIPS Agreement and Transfer of Technology, in K. P. Gallaghar
(ed.) Putting Development First (London: Zed Books).
Cortada, J . W. , and H. E. Eraser (2005), Mapping the Future in Science Intensive Industries:
Lessons from the Pharmaceutical Industry, IBM Systems Journal, 44, 163-183.
Danzon, P. M. (1997), Pharmaceutical Price Regulation: National Policies vs. Global Interests
(Washington: American Enterprise Institute).
Danzon, P. M. (1998), The Economics of Parallel Trade, Pharmacoeconomics, 13, 293-304.
Danzon, P. M., and A. Towse (2005), Theory and Implementation of Differential Pricing for
Pharmaceuticals, in K. E. Mascus and J. H. Reichman (eds. ), International Public
Goods and Transfer of Technology (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).
Danjon, P. M., J. McCullough, and S. Nicholson (2001), Efficiency in the Market for Biotech-
Pharmaceutical Alliances, University of Pennsylvania.
168 Economics of Biotechnology

Danjon, P.M., S. Nicholson, and N.S. Pereira (2005), Productivity in Pharmaceutical


Biotechnology R&D: The Role of Experience and Alliances, Journal of Health
Economics, 24, 317-339.
Decarolis, D.M., and D.L. Deeds (1999), The Impact of Stocks and Flows of Organizational
Knowledge on Firm Performance: An Empirical Investigation of the Biotechnology
Industry, Strategic Management Journal, 20, 953-968.
DeGarca, M., and D. Fonesca (2004), Institutions and Financial Requirements for the Emergence
of Biotechnology in Brazil, Presented at the Conference on Systems of Innovation and
Development of Third World Countries, Rio de Janeiro.
Dhar, T., and J.D. Foltz (2003), Market Structure and Consumer Valuation in the rBST-Free
and Organic Milk Markets, Working Paper FSWP 2003-2, Food System Research
Group, Madison.
Dickens, R.M. (2004), Biotechnology Foreseen and Forestalled: A Review Essay, Population
and Development Review, 30, 755-761.
DiMasi, J.A., R.W. Hansen, and H.G. Grabowski (2003), The Price of Innovation: New Estimates
of Drug development Costs, Journal of Health Economics, 22, 151-185.
Dixon, P., and C. Greenhalgh (2002), The Economics of Intellectual Property: A Review to
Identify Themes for Future Research, Oxford Intellectual Property Research Center,
Oxford.
Fafchamps, M. (1992), Solidarity Networks in Preindustrial Societies: Rational Peasants with
a Moral Economy, Economic Development and Cultural Change, 41, 147-174.
Falck-Zapeda, J.B., G. Traxler, and R.R. Nelson (2000), Surplus Distribution from the
Introduction of a Biotechnology Innovation, American Journal of Agricultural
Economics, 82, 360-369.
Falconi, C.A., S.W. Omamo, G.D’Toteren, and F. Iraqi (2001), An Ex ante Economic and Policy
Analysis of Research on Genetic Resistance to Livestock Disease: Trypanosomosis in
Africa, Agricultural Economics, 25, 153-163.
Fenn, G.W., N. Liang, and S. Prowse (1995), The Economics of the Private Equity Market,
Board of Governers of the Federal Reserve System.
Ferreira, E.J., and L.D. Brooks (2000), On Public Versus Private Equity Placements: Pedagogical
Illustrations, Financial Practice and Education, 241-248.
Filson, D., and R. Morales (2005), Equity Links and Information Acquisition in Biotechnology
Alliances, Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 59, 1-28.
Fink, C. (2000), How Stronger Patent Protection in India Might Affect the Behavior of
Transnational Pharmaceutical Industries, World Bank Working Paper WPS 2352.
Fisher, K., and D. Byerlee (2001), Managing Intellectual Property and Commercialization in
Public Research Organizations, The World Bank.
Foltz, J.D., and H.H. Chang (2002), The Adoption and Profitability of rBST on Connecticut
Dairy Farms, American Journal of Agricultural Economics, 84, 1021-1032.
References 169

Fontes, M. (2005), The Process of Transformation of Scientific and Technological Knowledge


into Economic Value Conducted by Biotechnology Spinoffs, Technovation, 25, 339-
347.
Frisvold, G.B., J. Sullivan, and A. Reneses (2003), Genetic Improvements in Major US Crops:
The Size and Distribution of Benefits, Agricultural Economics, 28, 109-119.
Fulton, M., and L. Keyowski (1999), The Producer Benefits of Herbicide Resistant Canola,
AgBioForum, 2, 85-93.
Fulton, M., and K. Giannakis (2001), Agricultural Biotechnology and Industry Structure,
AgBioForum, 4, 137-151.
Fulton, M., and K. Giannakas (2004), Inserting GM Products into the Food Chain: The Market
and Welfare Effects of Different Labeling and Regulatory Regimes, American Journal
of Agricultural Economics, 86, 42-60.
Galhardi, R.M. (1996), Trade Implications of Biotechnology in Developing Countries: A
Quantitative Assessment, Technology in Society, 18, 17-40.
Ganslandt, M., K.E. Maskus, and E.V. Wong (2001), Developing and Distributing Essential
Medicines to Poor Countries: The DEFEND Proposal, Unpublished Manuscript.
Garca, M., and D. Fonesca (2003), Institutional and Financial Requirements for the Emergence
of Biotechnology in Brazil, Unpublished Manuscript.
Gerpacio, R.V. (2003), The Role of Public Sector Versus Private Sector in R&D and Technology
Generation: The Case of Maize in Asia, Agricultural Economics, 29, 319-330.
Gersony, N. (1998), Applying a Three-Phase, Multi-Mission Strategic Framework to
Entreprenurial Biotechnology Companies, available at http://www.usabse.org/
knowledge/proceedings/1998/34-Gersony.pdf.
Gesche, A., A. Huslberger, and R.M. Enstsua-Mensah (2004), Towards a Global Code of
Ethics for Modern Foods and Agricultural Biotechnology, Queensland University of
Technology.
Giannakas, K., and M. Fulton (2002), Consumption Effects of Genetic Modification: What if
the Consumers are Right?, Agricultural Economics, 27, 97-109.
Giannakis, K., and A. Yiannaka (2004), The Market Potential of a New High-Oleic Soybean
: An Ex Ante Analysis, AgBioForum, 7, 101-122.
Giesecke, S. (2000), The Contrasting Roles of Government in the Development of Biotechnology
Industry in the US and Germany, Research Policy, 29, 205-223.
Gisselquist, D., and C.V. DerMeer (2001), Regulation for Seed and Fertilizer Markets, World
Bank Working Paper 22817.
Grabowski, H.G. (2002), Patents and New Product Development in the Pharmaceutical and
Biotechnology Industries, Proceedings of a Conference on Science and Cents: Exploring
the Economics of Biotechnology, available at http://www.dallasfed.org/research/
pubs/science/grabowski.pdf.
170 Economics of Biotechnology

Graff, G., D. Zilberman, and C. Yarkin (2001), The Role of Economic Research in the Evolution
of International Agricultural Biotechnology, in M. Qaim, A. Kattiger, and J. VonBraun
(eds.) Agricultural Biotechnology in Developing Countries: Towards Optimizing the
Benefits to the Poor (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers).
Guedj, I. (2004), Organizational Scope and Investment: Evidence from the Drug Development
Strategies and Performance of Biopharmaceutical Firms, NBER Working Paper 10933.
Gupta, A., and V. Chandak (2004), Agricultural Biotechnology in India: Ethics, Business, and
Politics, available at http://www.iimahd.ernet.in/publications/data/
2004_07_01anilgupta.pdf.
Hall, B.H. (2002), The Financing of Research and Development, Oxford Review of Economic
Policy, 16, 35-51.
Hall, B.H., and J.V. Reenen (2000), How Effective are Fiscal Incentives for R&D? A Review
of the Evidence, Research Policy, 29, 449-469.
Hamelink, C.N., G.V. Hooijdonk, and A.P.C. Faaij (2005), Ethanol from Lignocellulosic Biomass:
Techno-Economic Performance in Short-, Middle-, and Long-Term, Biomass and
Bioenergy, 28, 384-410.
Harhoff, D., and M. Reitzig (2004), Determinants of Opposition Against EPO Patent Grants
– The Case of Biotechnology and Pharmaceuticals, International Journal of Industrial
Organization, 22, 443-480.
Hayhurst, R. (2005), Norway Looks to Biotech as the Oil Starts to Run Out, Biotech Focus,
10, 387-390.
Henderson, R., and I. Cockburn (1996), Scale, Scope, and Spillovers: The Determinants of
Research Productivity in Drug Discovery, Rand Journal of Economics, 27, 32-39.
Horsch, R., and J. Montgomery (2004), Why We Partner: Collaboration Between the Private
and Public Sector for Food Security and Poverty Alleviation Through Agricultural
Biotechnology, AgBioForum, 7, 80-83.
Huang, J., R. Hu, S. Rozelle, F. Qiao, and C.E. Pray (2001), The Case of Cotton Farmers in
China, Working Paper 01-15, University of California, Davis. Available at http://
www.agecon.ucdavis.edu/facltypapers/rozelle/pdfs/cotton.pdf.
Huang, J., R. Hu, C. Pray, E. Qiao, and S. Rozelle (2003), Biotechnology as an Alternative
to Chemical Pesticides: A Case Study of Bt Cotton in China, Agricultural Economics,
29, 55-67.
Hubbell, B.J., M.C. Marra, and G.A. Carlson (2000), Estimating the Demand for a New
Technology: Bt Cotton and Insecticide Policies, American Journal of Agricultural
Economics, 82, 118-132.
Huffman, W.E., and R.E. Evenson (1992), Contributions of Public and Private Science and
Technology to U.S. Agricultural Productivity, American Journal of Agricultural
Economics, 74, 751-756.
References 171

Huygen, I., M. Veeman, and M. Lerohi (2004), Cost Implications of Alternative GM Tolerance
Levels: Non-Genetically Modified Wheat in Western Canada, AgBioForum, 6, 169-
177.
Ingley, A., J. Pavlik, and T. Smith (2002), Transgenic Protein Production as an Alternative
Manufacturing Technology for Pharmaceutical Companies, Kellogg School of
Management.
Inouye, B. (2002), Unpacking the Pharma Biotech Engines, Polaris Institute, Ottawa.
Isaac, G.E., M. Phillipson, and W.A. Kerr (2001), International Regulation of Trade in the
Products of Biotechnology, Estey Center for Law and Economics in International
Trade.
Ishibashi, I., and T. Matsumura (2005), R&D Competition Between Public and Private Sectors,
European Economic Review, to appear.
Jensen, M., and Meckling, W.H. (1976), Theory of the Firm: Managerial Behavior, Agency
Costs, and Ownership Structure, Journal of Financial Economics, 3, 305-360.
Jorgenson, D.W. (1983), Capital Theory and Investment Behavior, American Economic Review,
53, 247-255.
Just, R.E., and D.L. Heuth (1993), Multimarket Exploitation: The Case of Biotechnology and
Chemicals, American Journal of Agricultural Economics, 75, 936-945.
Kalaitzandokes, N. (1999), The Agricultural Knowledge System: Appropriate Roles and
Interactions for the Public and Private Sectors, AgBioForum, 2, 1-4.
Kapeleris, J., D. Hine, and R. Barnard (2004), Towards Definition of the Global Biotechnology
Value Chain Using Cases from Australian Biotechnology SMEs, International Journal
of Globalization and Small Business, 1, 79-91.
Kathuria, V., and V. Tewari (2004), Venture Capitalists and Biotech Sector – Discovering the
Potential, available at http://www.thehindubusinessonline.com/2004/12/29/stories/
2004122900200900.htm
Kathuria, V., and V. Tewari (2006), Vanture Capitalist’s Role in Choosing Entrepreneurs –
A Study of Indian Biotechnology Industry, Presented at the First Annual Max Plank
India Workshop, IISc, Bangalore.
Kawasaki, S., and J. McMillan (1987), The Design of Contracts: Evidence from Japanese
Subcontracting, Journal of Japanese and International Economics, 1, 327-349.
Kay, N., and W. McBride (2003), Production Contracts and Productivity in the U.S. Hog
Sector, American Journal of Agricultural Economics, 85, 121-133.
Khush, G.S. (2004), Biotechnology: Public-Private Partnerships and IPR in the Context of
Developing Countries, available at law.wustl.edu/centeris/Confpapers/
PDFWrdDoc/biotechkhush.pdf
Kim, Y.J. (2003), Determinants of Inter-Firm Technology Licensing: The Case of Licensors,
George Washington University, Washington.
172 Economics of Biotechnology

Klotz-Ingram, C., S. Jaus, J. Fernando-Cornejo, and W. McBride (1999), Farm Level Production
Effects Related to the Adoption of Genetically Modified Cotton for Pest Management,
AgBioForum, 2, 73-84.
Knight, F.H. (1933), Economic Organization (NewYork: Harper Torch Books).
Krattiger, A.F. (2004), Financing the Bioindustry and Facilitating Biotechnology Transfer, IP
Strategy Today, 8, 1-46.
Lakshmikumaran, M., and P. Phillip (2005), Patenting Biotechnology Innovations, Asian
Biotechnology and Development Review, 7, 25-41.
Lanjouw, J.O. (1997), The Introduction of Pharmaceutical Product Patents in India: “Heartless
Exploitation of the Poor and Suffering”, Center Discussion Paper no.775, Yale
University.
Lawlor, M.S. (2002), Biotechnology and Government Funding: Economic Motivation and
Policy Models, available at http://www.dallasfed.org/research/pubs/science/
lawlor.pdf.
Lehman, B.A. (2004), Intellectual Property and Compulsory Licensing: Pharmaceuticals and
the Developing World, Twelfth Annual Conference on International Intellectual
Property Law and Policy, New York.
Lehrer, M., and K. Asakawa (2004), Rethinking the Public Sector: Idiosyncracies of
Biotechnology Commercialization as Motors of National R&D Reform in Germany
and Japan, Research Policy, 33, 921-938.
Lemarie, S., and S. Marette (2002), Substitution and Complementarities in the Biotechnology
and Pesticide Markets: A Theoretical Framework, in N. Kalaitzandonakes (ed.)
Economic and Environmental Impacts of Agbiotech: A Global Perspective (Amsterdam:
Kluwer-Plenum).
Lemieux, C.M., and M.K. Wohlgenant (2001), Ex ante Evaluation of the Economic Impact of
Agricultural Biotechnology: The Case of Porcine Somatotropin, American Journal of
Agricultural Economics, 83, 903-914.
Lence, S.H., and D.J. Hayes (2003), Impact of Biotech Grains on Market Structure and Societal
Welfare, AgbioForum, 5, 85-89.
Lensink, R., R.V. Molen, and S. Gangopadhayay (2003), Business Groups, Financing
Constraints, and Investment: The Case of India, Journal of Development Studies, 40,
93-119.
Lerner, J., and R.P. Merges (1998), The Control of Technology Alliances: An Empirical Analysis
of the Biotechnology Industry, Journal of Industrial Economics, 46, 125-156.
Lerner, J., M. Shane, and A. Tsai (2003), Do Equity Cycles Matter? Evidence from Biotechnology
Alliances, Journal of Financial Economics, 67, 411-446.
Lesser, W. (1998), Intellectual Property Rights and Concentration in Agricultural Biotechnology,
AgBioForum, 1, 56-61.
References 173

Lichtenberg, E., and D. Zilberman (1986), The Econometrics of Damage Control: Why
Specification Matters, American Journal of Agricultural Economics, 68, 261-273.
Lichtenberg, F., and T.J. Philipson (2002), The Dual Effects of Intellectual Property Regulations:
Within and Between Patent Competition in the U.S. Pharmaceutical Industry, Journal
of Law and Economics, 45, 643-672.
Liebskind, J.P., A.L. Oliver, L. Zucker, and M. Brewer (1996), Social Networks, Learning, and
Flexibility: Sourcing Scientific Knowledge in New Biotechnology Firms, Organization
Science, 7, 428-443.
Lusk, J.L., L.O. House, C. Velli, S.R. Jaeger, M. Moore, B. Morrow, and W. Bruce Truill (2005),
Consumer Welfare Effects of Introducing and Labeling Genetically Modified Food,
Economics Letters, 88, 382-388.
MacDonald, J.M., M.C. Ahearn, and D.Banker (2004), Organizational Economics in Agriculture
Policy Analysis, American Journal of Agricultural Economics, 86, 744-749.
Malerba, F., and I. Orsenigo (2002), Innovation and Market Structure in the Dynamics of the
Pharmaceutical Industry and Biotechnology: Towards a History Friendly Model,
Industrial and Corporate Change, 11, 667-703.
Maltbarger, R., and N. Kalaitzandokes (2000), Direct and Hidden Costs in Identity Preserving
Supply Chains, AgBioForum, 3, 236-242.
Mangematin, V., S. Lemarie, J.P. Bossin, D. Catherine, F. Corolleur, R. Coronini, and M.
Trommetter (2003), Development of SMEs and Heterogenity of Trajectories: The Case
of Biotechnology in France, Research Policy, 32, 621-638.
Maria, A. (2003), Biotechnology in India, Report by the French Embassy in India.
Maria, A., and S.V. Ramani (2004), Trips and its Possible Impact on the Indian
Biopharmaceutical Industry, Presented at the Conference on Market for
Pharmaceuticals and the Health of Developing Nations, Toulouse.
Maskus, K.E. (2001), Parallel Imports in Pharmaceuticals: Implications for Competition and
Prices in Developing Countries, Report to the World Intellectual Property Organization.
McGloughlin, M. (1999), Ten Reasons Why Biotechnology Will be Important to the Developing
World, AgBioForum, 2, 163-174.
Monsanto (2003), 2003 Monsanto Contract, Available at
http://www.non-gen-farmers.com/news_details.asp?ID-613.
Mizoan, S. (2000), Biotechnology, Environment, and Regulations, University of Georgia.
Moon, W., and S.K. Balasubramanian (2001), Public Perceptions and Willingness to Pay a
Premium for non-GM Foods in the US and UK, AgBioForum, 4, 221-231.
Morse, S., R. Bennett, and Y. Ismael (2005), Comparing the Performance of Official and
Unofficial Genetically Modified Cotton in India, AgBioForum, 8, 1-6.
Moschini, G.C. (2001), Economic Benefits and Costs of Biotechnology Innovations in
Agriculture, Working Paper 01-WP264, Iowa State University.
174 Economics of Biotechnology

Moschini, G.C. (2001), Biotech – Who Wins? Economic Benefits and Costs of Biotechnology
Innovations in Agriculture, The Estey Center Journal of International Law and Trade
Policy, 2, 93-117.
McMillan, G.S., F. Narin, and D.L. Deeds (2000), An Analysis of the Critical Role of Public
Science in Innovation: The Case of Biotechnology, Research Policy, 29, 1-8.
Newell, P. (2003), Biotech Firms, Biotech Politics: Negotiating GMOs in India, IDS Working
Paper 201.
Niosi, J. (2003), Alliances are Not Enough Explaining Rapid Growth in Biotechnology Firms,
Research Policy, 32, 737-750.
Noll, J. (2004), Comparing Quality Signals as Tools of Consumer Protection: Are Warranties
Always Better than Advertisements to Promote Higher Product Quality?, International
Review of Law and Economics, 24, 227-239.
Noussair, C., S. Robin, and B. Ruffieux (2004), Do Consumers Really Refuse to Buy Genetically
Modified Foods?, Economic Journal, 114, 102-120.
OECD (2002), Genetic Inventions, Intellectual Property Rights and Licensing Practices.
OECD (2004), Biotechnology for Sustainable Growth and Development.
Oehmke, J. (2002), Biotechnology R&D Races, Industry Structure, and Public and Private
Sector Research Orientation, AgBioForum, 4, 105-114.
Oehmke, J., and C.A. Wolf (2003), Measuring Concentration in the Biotechnology R&D
Industry: Adjusting for Interfirm Transfer of Genetic Materials, AgBioForum, 6, 134-
140.
Oehmke, J., M. Mywish, and D. Weatherspoon (2001), The Effects of Biotechnology Policy
on Trade and Growth, The Estey Center Journal of International Law and Trade
Policy, 2, 283-306.
Office of Technology Assessment (1984), Commercial Biotechnology – An International
Analysis (Washington: Government Printing Office).
Oh, V.M.S. (2002), Should Ethical Issues in Biotechnology Research be Decided by Physician
Scientists or by Lawyers?, Annals of the Academy of Medicine, 31, 137-139.
Orsenigo, L. (1989), The Emergence of Biotechnology: Institutions and Markets in Industrial
Innovation (NewYork: St. Martin’s Press).
Orsenigo, L., F. Pamolli, and M. Ricaboni (2001), Technological Change and Network Dynamics
Lessons From the Pharmaceutical Industry, Research Policy, 30, 485-508.
Palnitkar, U. (2002), Biotechnology in India, Ernst & Young, Hyderabad.
Perrin, R., and L. Falginiti (2001), Dynamic Pricing of Genetically Modified Crop Traits,
Presented at the 5th International Conference on Biotechnology, Science, and Modern
Agriculture, Ravello, Italy.
Perry, J.N. (2003), GM Crops and the Environment, available at www.rotheyhouse.co.uk.
References 175

Powell, W.W., K.W. Koput, and L. Smith-Doerr (1996), Interorganizational Collaboration and
the Locus of Innovation: Networks of Learning in Biotechnology, Administrative
Science Quarterly, 41, 116-145.
Powell, W.W., K.W. Koput, L. Smith-Doerr, and J. Owen-Smith (1999), Network Position and
Firm Performance: Organizational Returns to Collaboration in the Biotechnology
Industry, in S. Andrews and D. Knoke (eds.) Networks In and Around Organizations
(Greenwich: Jai Press).
Pyka, A., and P.P. Saviotti (2000), Innovation Networks in Biotechnology, The SEIN Project.
Qaim, M. (2001), A Prospective Evaluation of Biotechnology in Semi-Subsistence Agriculture,
Agricultural Economics, 25, 165-175.
Qaim, M. (2003), Bt Cotton in India: Field Trial Results and Economic Projections, World
Development, 31, 2115-2127.
Rai, A.K. (2005), Property Rights and Collective Action: The Case of Biotechnology Research
with Low Commercial Value, in K.E. Mascus and J.H. Reichman (eds.), International
Public Goods and Transfer of Technology (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).
Rai, A.K. (2005a), Open and Collaborative Research: A New Model for Biomedicine, in R.
Hahn (ed.) Intellectual Property Rights in Frontier Industries: Software and Biotech
(Washington: Brookings Press).
Rai, A.K. (2005b), Property Rights and Collective Action: The Case of Biotechnology Research
with Low Commercial Value, in K.E. Maskus and J.H. Reichman (eds.) International
Public Goods and Transfer of Technology Under a Globalized Intellectual Property
Regime (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).
Raina, R. (2003), Biotechnology in the National Agricultural Research System: A Case for
Institutional Reform, Asian Biotechnology and Development Review, 5, 27-56.
Ramani, S.V. (2002), Who is Interested in Biotech? R&D Strategies, Knowledge Base and
Market Sales of Indian Biopharmaceutical Firms, Research Policy, 31, 381-398.
Rangnekar, D. (2006), No Pills for Poor People? Economic and Political Weekly, 41, 409-417.
Ricaboni, M., and E. Pammoli (2002), On Firm Growth in Networks, Research Policy, 31,
1405-1416.
Robinson, J. (1999), Ethics and Transgenic Crops: A Review, Electronic Journal of
Biotechnology, 2, 71-81.
Roijakkers, N., J. Hagedoorn, and H.V. Kranenberg (2005), Dual Market Structures and the
Likelihood of Repeated Ties—Evidence from Pharmaceutical Biotechnology, Research
Policy, 34, 235-245.
Rothaermal, F.T. (2001), Complementary Assets, Strategic Alliances, and the Incumbent’s
Advantage: An Empirical Study of Industry and Firm Effects in the Biopharmaceutical
Industry, Research Policy, 30, 1235-1251.
Rothaermal, F.T., and D.L. Deeds (2004), Exploration and Exploitation Alliances in
Biotechnology: A System of New Product Development, Strategic Management Journal,
25, 201-221.
176 Economics of Biotechnology

Sampath, P.G. (2004), Agricultural Biotechnology: Issues for Biosafety Governance in Asian
Countries, United Nations University Working Paper 2004-13.
Schall, B.A. (2004), Biodiversity, Biotechnology, and the Environment, Washington University.
Schimmelpfenning, D.E., C.E. Pray, and M.F. Brennan (2004), The Impact of Seed Industry
Concentration on Innovation: A Study of US Biotech Market Leaders, Agricultural
Economics, 30, 157-167.
Shan, W., J.P. Morgan, and J. Song (1997), Foreign Direct Investment and the Sourcing of
Technological Advantage: Evidence from the Biotechnology Industry, Journal of
International Business Studies, 28, 267-284.
Shavell, S., and T. Van Ypersele (2001), Rewards Versus Intellectual Property Rights, Journal
of Law and Economics, 44, 525-547.
Shoemaker, R. (2001), Economic Issues in Agricultural Biotechnology, Washington D.C., U.S.
Department of Agriculture.
Sonka, S., and S. Pueppke (1999), Exploring the Public’s Role in Agricultural Biotechnology
Research, AgBioForum, 2, 33-36.
Sporleder, J., and L.A. Moses (2004), Knowledge Capital, Intangible Assets, and Leverage:
Evidence from U.S. Agricultural Biotechnology Firms, International Food and
Agribusiness Management Review, 7, 26-36.
Strohmenger, R., and A. Wambach (2000), Adverse Selection and Categorical Discrimination
in Health Insurance Markets: The Effects of Genetic Tests, Journal of Health Economics,
19, 197-218.
Stuart, T.E. (2000), Interorganizational Alliances and the Performance of Firms: A Study of
Growth and Innovation Rates in a High Technology Industry, Strategic Management
Journal, 21, 791-811.
Subramanian, A. (1995), Putting Some Numbers on the TRIPS Pharmaceutical Debate,
International Journal of Technology Management, 10, 252-265.
Teece, D.J. (19890), Towards an Economic Theory of the Multiproduct Firm, Journal of
Economic Behavior and Organization, 1, 237-247.
Thompson, P. (2000), Food and Agricultural Biotechnology: Incorporating Ethical
Considerations, Canadian Biotechnology Advisory Committee Project.
Traore, N., and A. Rose (2003), Determinants of Biotechnology Utilization by the Canadian
Industry, Research policy, 32, 1719-1735.
Traxler, G. (2004), The Economic Impacts of Biotechnology Based Technological Innovation,
ESA Working Paper No. 04-08, FAO.
Vanloqueren, G., and P.A. Baret (2005), Systemic “Relevance” Assessment of Transgenic
Crops: Bridging Biotechnology Regulations and Sustainable Development Policies,
Unpublished Manuscript, Catholic University of Louvain.
Wally, T. (2000), Outcomes Research and Biotechnology Products: A European View, Drug
Information Journal, 34, 185-192.
References 177

Watal, J. (2000), Intellectual Property Rights (New Delhi: Oxford University Press).
Watal, J. (1996), Introducing Product Patents in Indian Pharmaceutical Sector, World
Competition, 20, 7-21.
Watal, J. (2000), Pharmaceutical Patents, Prices and Welfare Losses: Policy Options for India
Under WTO TRIPS Agreement, World Economy, 23, 733-752.
Watal, J. (2001), Workshop on Differential Pricing and Financing of Essential Drugs, WTO
Secretariat.
Watal, J., and A.P. Mathai (1995), Sectoral Impact of the Uruguay Round Agreements on
Developing Countries: Pharmaceutical Industry, UNIDO.
Watson, J.D. (1969), The Double Helix (New York: Penguin).
Weavaer, R.D. and J. Wesseler (2004), Monopolistic Pricing Power for Transgenic Crops
when Technology Adopters Face Irreversible Benefits and Costs, Applied Economics
Letters, 11, 969-973.
Wiktorowicz, M., and R. Deber (1997), Regulating Biotechnology: A Rational Political Model
of Policy development, Health Policy, 40, 115-138.
Williamson, O.E. (1988), Corporate Governance and Corporate Finance, Journal of Finance,
43, 567-591.
Williamson, O.E. (1991), Comparative Economic Organization: The Analysis of Discrete
Structural Alternatives, Administrative Science Quarterly, 36, 269-296.
Williamson, O.E. (2002), The Theory of the Firm as a Governance Structure: From Choice to
Contract, Journal of Economic Perspectives, 16, 171-196.
Wolf, S., and D. Zilberman (1999), Public Science, Biotechnology, and the Industrial
Organization of the Agrofood System, AgBioForum, 2, 37-42.
Zilberman, D., C. Yarkin, and A. Heiman (1997), Agricultural Biotechnology: Economic and
International Implications, Presented at the International Agricultural Economics
Association Meetings at Sacramento, California.
Zilberman, D., H. Ameden, G. Graff, and M. Qaim (2004), Agricultural Biotechnology:
Productivity, Biodiversity, and Intellectual Property Rights, Journal of Agricultural
& Food Industrial Organization, 2, Article 3.
Zucker, L.G., and M. Darby (1995), Virtuous Cycles of Productivity: Star Bioscientists and
the Institutional Transformation of Industry, NBER Working Paper 5342.
Zucker, L.G., and M.R. Darby (1997), Present at the Biotechnological Revolution:
Transformation of Technological Identity for a Large Incumbent Pharmaceutical Firm,
Research Policy, 26, 429-446.
Zucker, L.G., M.R. Darby, and J. Armstrong (2002), Commercializing Knowledge: University
Science, Knowledge Capture, and Firm Performance in Biotechnology, Management
Science, 48, 138-153.
178 Economics of Biotechnology

Zucker, L.G., M.R. Darby, and M.B. Brewer (1998), Intellectual Human Capital and the Birth
of U.S. Biotechnology Enterprises, American Economic Review, 88, 290-306.
Zylbersztajn, D., and S.G. Lazzarini (2005), On the Survival of Contracts: Assessing the
Stability of Technology Licensing Agreements in the Brazilian Seed Industry, Journal
of Economic Behavior and Organization, 56, 108-120.

You might also like